General Equilibrium with Risk Loving, Friedman-Savage and other Preferences

Similar documents
Participation in Risk Sharing under Ambiguity

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Instituto de Matemática Pura e Aplicada

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

(Ir)rational Exuberance: Optimism, Ambiguity and Risk

General Equilibrium under Uncertainty

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

Prevention and risk perception : theory and experiments

Background Risk, Demand for Insurance, and Choquet Expected Utility Preferences

EXTRA PROBLEMS. and. a b c d

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Bargaining and Competition Revisited Takashi Kunimoto and Roberto Serrano

Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Mock Examination 2010

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

1 Dynamic programming

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

Economia Financiera Avanzada

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Assets with possibly negative dividends

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

Consumption and Asset Pricing

Price Theory of Two-Sided Markets

Ambiguity, ambiguity aversion and stores of value: The case of Argentina

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

The text book to this class is available at

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Macro 1: Exchange Economies

Gains from Trade. Rahul Giri

Ambiguity Aversion in Standard and Extended Ellsberg Frameworks: α-maxmin versus Maxmin Preferences

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

PURE-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA WITH NON-EXPECTED UTILITY PLAYERS

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Economia Financiera Avanzada

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

Payment mechanisms and risk-aversion in electricity markets with uncertain supply

Behavioral Competitive Equilibrium and Extreme Prices. Faruk Gul Wolfgang Pesendorfer Tomasz Strzalecki

Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity. Tomasz Strzalecki (Harvard University) Jan Werner (University of Minnesota)

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints

MATH3075/3975 FINANCIAL MATHEMATICS TUTORIAL PROBLEMS

Course Handouts - Introduction ECON 8704 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Uncertainty Improves the Second-Best

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Chapter II: Labour Market Policy

Ex Ante Regulation and Ex Post Liability Under Uncertainty 1

Workshop on the pricing and hedging of environmental and energy-related financial derivatives

Speculative Trade under Ambiguity

Interest Rates and Currency Prices in a Two-Country World. Robert E. Lucas, Jr. 1982

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Ambiguous Pricing and Financial Market Imperfections

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

Practice Problems 1: Moral Hazard

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders. Michael Ostrovsky

Non-Monotonicity of the Tversky- Kahneman Probability-Weighting Function: A Cautionary Note

Homework 3: Asset Pricing

Finish what s been left... CS286r Fall 08 Finish what s been left... 1

Lecture 2: Stochastic Discount Factor

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

Chair of Communications Theory, Prof. Dr.-Ing. E. Jorswieck. Übung 5: Supermodular Games

Topic 4. Introducing investment (and saving) decisions

Reference Dependence Lecture 1

Chapter 2 Equilibrium and Efficiency

Winners and Losers from Price-Level Volatility: Money Taxation and Information Frictions

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Prospect Theory: A New Paradigm for Portfolio Choice

Answers to June 11, 2012 Microeconomics Prelim

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Chapter 3 Introduction to the General Equilibrium and to Welfare Economics

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Behavioral Insurance: An Introduction

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

University of California Berkeley

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Eliciting Objective Probabilities via Lottery Insurance Games

A Theoretical Foundation for the Stakeholder Corporation

Problem Set 3. Thomas Philippon. April 19, Human Wealth, Financial Wealth and Consumption

Optimizing S-shaped utility and risk management

BACKGROUND RISK IN THE PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODEL. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama. and. Paul D. Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas

Contents. Expected utility

Endogenous choice of decision variables

Why Bankers Should Learn Convex Analysis

Macroeconomics and finance

In Diamond-Dybvig, we see run equilibria in the optimal simple contract.

Risk Measures and Optimal Risk Transfers

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Speculative Bubble Burst

Choice under Uncertainty

Incentive Compatibility: Everywhere vs. Almost Everywhere

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #8b - Uncertainty II

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

MORAL HAZARD AND BACKGROUND RISK IN COMPETITIVE INSURANCE MARKETS: THE DISCRETE EFFORT CASE. James A. Ligon * University of Alabama.

Transcription:

General Equilibrium with Risk Loving, Friedman-Savage and other Preferences A. Araujo 1, 2 A. Chateauneuf 3 J.Gama-Torres 1 R. Novinski 4 1 Instituto Nacional de Matemática Pura e Aplicada 2 Fundação Getúlio Vargas 3 Université de Paris 1 4 Faculdades Ibmec-RJ August 17,2015

Introduction Our Results We prove that with sufficient Aggregate Risk, equilibrium exists, even with a finite number of agents, for a very large class of preferences. For Rank-Dependent preferences, there is risk-sharing for these equilibria. We provide robust examples in which: 1 The Risk-Loving decreases the volatility and improves the welfare. 2 Regulation increases volatility and reduces welfare.

Content 1 Existence of Equilibrium Example in the Edgeworth Box Expected Utility case Extensions to other preferences 2 RDEU model, Risk Sharing and Volatility Risk sharing with ambiguity 3 Risk-Loving Decreases Volatility Volatility and Welfare Example with Risk Loving Example with Two Risk Averters 4 Model with Friedman Savage Decision Makers Example with a Friedman-Savage Decision Maker Model with Friedman Savage and Prospect Theory

Example in the Edgeworth Box Two states of nature. Utility: U i (x 1,x 2 ) = 1 2 ui (x 1 ) + 1 2 ui (x 2 ). Agent 1: u 1 (x) = lnx, ω 1 = ( ) ω1 1,ω1 2 > 0, with an Arrow-Debreu constraint. Agent 2: u 2 (x) = x 2, ω 2 = ( ) ω1 2,ω2 2 > 0, with an Arrow-Debreu constraint. ω 1 := ω 1 1 + ω2 1 and ω 2 := ω 1 2 + ω2 2.

Since u 2 is convex, any optimal allocation must satisfy x 2 1 = 0 or x 2 2 = 0 for any price (p,1 p). In fact x2 2 = 0 p 1/2 and under the FOC and Market Clearing p = ω 2 + ω 2 2 ω 1 1 + ω 2 + ω 2 2 1 2 ω1 1 ω 2 + ω 2 2, and analogously we have x 2 1 = 0 ω1 2 ω 1 + ω 2 1.

Then Existence of Equilibrium ω 1 1 ω 2 + ω 2 2 or ω 1 2 ω 1 + ω 2 1 ω 1 ω 2 ω 2 1 + ω2 2 or ω 2 ω 1 ω 2 1 + ω2 2. Remark There exists equilibrium if and only if 1 there is a difference of AT LEAST of ω1 2 + ω2 2 among the aggregate endowments i. e. there should be enough aggregate risk, or 2 the aggregate risk must be bigger or equal of the total wealth of the risk lover, or 3 the risk averter should be sufficiently rich in one of the state.

Edgeworth Box ( x 1,x 2) ω 2 1 Risk Lover ω 2 2 ( ω 1,ω 2) ω 1 2 Risk Averter ω 1 1

Existence of Equilibrium Expected Utility case Let S states. Probability π = (π 1,...,π S ) 0, I + J Expected Utility agents, I are Risk Averse, J are Risk Lovers.

Existence of Equilibrium Risk Averters u i is: Strictly monotone, Concave, C 1 (0, ), limx u i (x) = 0 and Endowments are ω1 i,...,ωi S > 0 for each i. With an AD constraint.

Existence of Equilibrium Risk Lovers u i is: Strictly monotone and Convex. Endowments are ω1 i,...,ωi S > 0 for each i. λ i s [ 0,ω i s] a minimal consumption imposed in the state s. And with an AD constraint.

Existence of Equilibrium Main Result Theorem Let U i and { ωs i } fixed except in the state 1. If there is a K > 0 such that i,r i I ω1 i K then there is an equilibrium for the economy with p S 1 ++. Extension for more than one state Proof of Theorem Lemma Given a price p, all risk lovers will choose a consumption plan x i such that { λ i xs i s for s s 0 (minimal consumption), = [ pω i s s0 p s λs i ] for some s 0. 1 p s0

With rationing on the amount of risk taken by the Risk/Ambiguity lovers. Existence of Equilibrium Extensions to other preferences Smooth Ambiguity Decision Makers, Klibanoff, Marinacci and Mukerji, Econometrica (2005). Choquet Expected Utility, Schmeidler Econometrica (1989). Variational Preferences, Macheroni, Marinacci and Rustichini Econometrica (2006). Friedman Savage Decision Makers, Friedman and Savage JPE (1948). Friedman Savage case Rank-Dependent Expected Utility (RDEU), Quiggin Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization (1982), Kluwer Academic Publishers (1993) and Yaari Econometrica (1987).

RDEU model, Risk Sharing and Volatility Each agent distorts the prior π with f i, where f i Continuous, f i (0) = 0 and f i (1) = 1. u i concave, f i is convex = Ambiguity Averse (pessimism). u i convex, f i is concave = Ambiguity Lovers (optimism). And the utility function is: U i (x) = (C) 0 u i x df i ( π = f i π [ u i x t ] 1 ) dt + f i π [ u i x t ] dt 0

Study of Volatility and Regulation Implementation with complete markets GOAL: To evaluate the impact of Risk Loving on Volatility and Regulation. We interpret the AD equilibrium as a financial market equilibrium with two states with probability (π 1,π 2 ) with no consumption in t = 0.

Study of Volatility and Regulation Implementation with complete markets Consider two assets: 1.1 1.4 Bond Risky asset 1.1 0.95 Constraints: at t = 0, qα + β = 0 at t = 1, ω i s + R s α + Rβ λ i s for each s. Volatility formula

Risk-Loving Decreases Volatility Two states of nature, f i (x) = x, U i (x) = 1 2 ui (x 1 ) + 1 2 ui (x 2 ) where u i (x) = 1 ρ i ( 1 e ρi x ) Agent 1: Agent 2: ρ 1 = 1 ρ 2 [ 1,1] ω 1 = (4,1) ω 2 = (2,1)

Risk-Loving Decreases Volatility Volatility and Welfare 0.55 0.5 0.45 Increasing Volatility 1.4 1.2 Welfare Losses Risk Averse Risk Lover/Averse Standard Deviation 0.4 0.35 0.3 0.25 Utility Level 1 0.8 0.6 0.4 0.2 0.2 1 0.8 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1 Propension Aversion 0 1 0.8 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1 Propension Aversion In presence of Aggregate Risk, Risk Loving absorbs most of the risk reducing Volatility. Also there is a reduction in Welfare when there is less Risk Loving in the economy.

Effects of Regulation Two states of nature, f i (x) = x, U i (x) = 1 2 ui (x 1 ) + 1 2 ui (x 2 ) where u i (x) = 1 ρ i ( 1 e ρi x ) Agent 1: Agent 2: Agent 3: ρ 1 = 1 ρ 2 = 1.5 ρ 3 = 1 ω 1 = (2,1) ω 2 = (2,1) ω 3 = (1,1) λ 3 [0,1]

Effects of Regulation There is regulation on the risk lover s consumption x 3 s λ 3 [0,1] then λ 3 = 0 means no regulation. λ 3 = 1 means regulation impose the consumption to be (1,1).

Effects of Regulation Volatility and Welfare Price Standard deviation Utility 1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.4 Volatility 1.1 1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.4 Utility levels Less Ambiguity Averse More Ambiguity Averse Ambiguity Lover 0.3 0.3 0.2 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 Regulation 0.2 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 Regulation λ 3 increases = Volatility increases Remark Regulation increases Volatility and reduces Welfare in the economy.

What if there is no Risk Lover? Example with Two Risk Averters New economy only with the two Risk Averse defined before. Now the two agents are under regulation. x i s λ i = λ [0,1]

What if there is no Risk Lover? Effects of Regulation 0.57 Regulation Vs Volatility 0.5605 Regulation Vs Utility 0.56 Less Pessimistic Price Standard Deviation 0.55 0.54 0.53 0.52 0.51 0.56 0.5595 0.559 0.5585 More Pessimistic 0.5 0.49 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 Regulation 0.558 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 Regulation Remark The regulation affects volatility and welfare only when it is unrealistically tight ( i.e., λ > 0.95 ), since regulation is not binding for λ < 0.95.

Model with Friedman-Savage Decision Makers Instead of Risk Lovers, consider Expected Utility agents with u : [0, ) R concave in [0,x c ] [ x,infty) and convex in [x c, x) where x c 0 and x x c. u(x) Proposition x c If the aggregate endowment of risk averters is sufficiently large in 0 < S 1 < S states compared with other states, there is an equilibrium for the economy with p S 1 ++. x x

Friedman-Savage Case Example and Volatility For the agent 1: u 1 (x) = ln(x), ω1 1 = 5 2.5a, ω1 2 = 2 a. For the agent 2: ln(x) + (1/2)x 2 if x 3/2, u 2 (x) = 13/6(x 3/2) + 9/8 + log(3/2) if x > 3/2. u 2 has an inflection point at x c = 1, ω 2 1 = 2.5a, ω2 2 = a, where a [0,1].

Volatility 8 7 Proportion among consumptions Risk Averter Friedman-Savage Agent Volatility Vs variation on Friedman-Savage wealth 2.3 2.28 Proportion x 1 /x 2 6 5 4 3 2.26 2.24 2.22 2.2 2.18 2 2.16 1 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 FS Wealth 2.14 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 FS Wealth Remark FS Decision Maker behaves more as a Risk Lover and less as a Risk Averter when his wealth increases. This implies a reduction on volatility. Back to extensions

Model with Friedman Savage and Prospect Theory Remark A FS Decision maker with x c = 0 is consistent with Kahneman and Tversky (1992) with the weighting function as the identity when the second inflection point satisfies x = ω s for all s. Remark A FS Decision maker is consistent with Jullien and Salanié (2000) with the weighting function as the identity when the the second inflection point satisfies x = ω s for all s. Proposition For preferences mentioned above instead of Risk lovers, under the conditions mentioned in the proposition above, there is an equilibrium for the economy with p S 1 ++.

Model with Friedman Savage and Prospect Theory Remark For general distorsions of an objective probability. If the endowment distributions are such that ω s1 ω s2 for each pair of states s 1,s 2, there is an equilibrium for the economy with p S 1 ++ under the conditions mentioned in the proposition above. Notice that this is not inconsistent with Azevedo and Gottlieb (2012) since, in our framework, there is only a finite number of states.

Thank you!

Remark For preferences given by an Expected Utility agent with a Friedman-Savage (1948) utility index or a Kahneman and Tversky (1992) agent with a reference point x = ωs I +j > 0 j and the capacity for losses is such that the functional V ( ) is convex, there is an optimal solution for the consumer problem with an AD constrain in which there is AT MOST one state in which the agent consumes in the convex part of the utility index or value function. Remark Notice that if V is no convex for losses, the only possible form to ensure equilibrium is increasing, even more, the aggregate risk to ensure that all agents consume 0 for all given by the Prospect Theory if their consumption is in the losses part.

Existence of Equilibrium Extension for more that one state Proposition Given { ωs i } if there exist R states 1 s s,i 1,...,s R S and 0 < k < K, with K sufficiently big such that: 1 π s1 = = π sr, 2 J = RJ with J N and ω I +j 1 = ω I +j 2 for j 1 = jr + l 1 and j 2 = jr + l 2 where 1 l 1,l 2 R and 0 j < R, 3 i I ω i s r K and i>i ω i s r k for all r = 1,...,R, 4 i ω i s k for s r s r = 1,...,R, 5 there exists α [0,1] such that λ i s = αω i s for each s and i > I. Then there is an equilibrium for the economy with p S 1 ++. Main Theorem

Existence of Equilibrium Proof. Define a modified generalized game with I + J + 1 players. For each Risk Averse, define a player as usual. For each Risk Lover: Utility: V i (p,x) := x 1. Set of actions: x X i := {( x 1,λ2,...,λ i S i ) : λ i }{{} 1 x 1 2ω }. minimal cons. Restriction: B i (p) := { x X i : px pω i}.

Existence of Equilibrium Proof. (Cont) The last player is the traditional market: Utility: V i (p,x) := i ( px i pω i). Set of actions: p S 1 +. Restriction: S 1 +. ( (x We have Existence of Nash Equilibrium i ) ) I +J i=1,p which satisfies i x i = i ω i and optimization for the Risk Averse. Missing: Optimality of consumptions for Risk Lovers in the original economy.

Existence of Equilibrium Proof. (Cont) Using the First Order Conditions for the Risk Averse, lim x u i (x) = 0 and lim x 0 u i (x) = we have: i I ω i 1 K with K big enough and x i 1 > 0 i = 1,...,I = p 1 0. And similarly, for each state s 1 the previous condition implies that p s must be bounded from below and far away from zero.

Existence of Equilibrium Proof. (Cont) And as consequence of p 1 0 and p s bounded and far away from zero for s 1. Then the Risk Lovers will specialize in state 1 and the Nash Equilibrium allocation will be also optimal for the Risk Lovers. And finally the Nash Equilibrium allocation will be also an equilibrium for the economy. Main Theorem

Formula for Volatility Volatility of returns: R 1 σ(q) = π 1 q µ(q) + (1 π 1) R 2 q µ(q), where µ(q) = π 1 R 1 q + (1 π 1 ) R 2 q. Finantial Equilibrium