What are the additional assumptions that must be satisfied for Rabin s theorem to hold?

Similar documents
Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260

Altruism. Voluntary contributions to public goods in large economies (Corrected after the lecture) Readings

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture XI: Oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand Competition

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1)

Chapter 33: Public Goods

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Social preferences I and II

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

Supplement to the lecture on the Diamond-Dybvig model

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Topic 3 Social preferences

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Summary The Justifiability and Sustainability of the Corporate Management Inconsistent

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Mock Examination 2010

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

8/28/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 2 nd lecture. Expected utility. What is a lottery?

Chapter 7 Review questions

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

8/31/2011. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. Suggested approximation (See Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) The value function (see Benartzi and Thaler, 1995)

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Econ 101A Final Exam We May 9, 2012.

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Intertemporal choice: Consumption and Savings

Psychology and Economics Field Exam August 2012

Kutay Cingiz, János Flesch, P. Jean-Jacques Herings, Arkadi Predtetchinski. Doing It Now, Later, or Never RM/15/022

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Today. Applications of NE and SPNE Auctions English Auction Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

Graduate Macro Theory II: Two Period Consumption-Saving Models

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

w E(Q w) w/100 E(Q w) w/

Lecture 5. ECON 4910, Environmental Economics Spring Enforcement (cont.) Voluntary contributions to public goods. Voluntary term paper

Exercises for Chapter 8

Intermediate microeconomics. Lecture 1: Introduction and Consumer Theory Varian, chapters 1-5

Elements of Economic Analysis II Lecture X: Introduction to Game Theory

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

Microeconomics II Lecture 8: Bargaining + Theory of the Firm 1 Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics December 2016

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

Economics Honors Exam Review (Micro) Mar Based on Zhaoning Wang s final review packet for Ec 1010a, Fall 2013

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

All Equilibrium Revenues in Buy Price Auctions

Total /20 /30 /30 /20 /100. Economics 142 Midterm Exam NAME Vincent Crawford Winter 2008

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

Lecture 3: Prospect Theory, Framing, and Mental Accounting. Expected Utility Theory. The key features are as follows:

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

that internalizes the constraint by solving to remove the y variable. 1. Using the substitution method, determine the utility function U( x)

ECMC49S Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

Applying Risk Theory to Game Theory Tristan Barnett. Abstract

Department of Economics, UCB

Chapter 19 Optimal Fiscal Policy

Rationalizable Strategies

Game Theory Lecture #16

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

ECONOMICS 336Y5Y Fall/Spring 2014/15. PUBLIC ECONOMICS Spring Term Test February 26, 2015

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Problem Set 1. Debraj Ray Economic Development, Fall 2002

Mental-accounting portfolio

EconS Games with Incomplete Information II and Auction Theory

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2011 Examination. 2010/2011 Syllabus ONLY

Online Appendix: Extensions

Optimal Actuarial Fairness in Pension Systems

Name: Midterm #1 EconS 425 (February 20 th, 2015)

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

January 26,

Characterization of the Optimum

Microeconomics Comprehensive Exam

Transcription:

Exam ECON 4260, Spring 2013 Suggested answers to Problems 1, 2 and 4 Problem 1 (counts 10%) Rabin s theorem shows that if a person is risk averse in a small gamble, then it follows as a logical consequence that the person is extremely risk averse in large gambles provided that some additional assumptions are satisfied. (For concreteness, think of a small gamble as one where potential gains and losses are less than 100 kroner, while in a large gamble the potential gains can be in millions of kroner.) What are the additional assumptions that must be satisfied for Rabin s theorem to hold? The required premises for the argument are that the person is risk averse in the small gamble, for any level of wealth and that the person maximizes expected utility. Rabin s argument takes for granted that the argument in the utility function is wealth + gains/losses from the lottery. While not formally an assumption, more an interpretation of expected utility, there may be a bonus for mentioning that. Problem 2 (counts 20%) Consider the following choices. Choice 1: You first get 400 kroner, and then you have to choose between A: Losing 500 kroner or winning 500 kroner with equal probability. B: Losing 100 kroner with 100% probability. Choice 2: You have to pay 100 kroner, and then you get to choose between C: Winning 1000 kroner or 0 kroner with equal probability. D: Winning 400 kroner with 100% probability. Consider Ann s and Ola s preferences in these two choices. a) Ann maximizes expected utility. She prefers B over A in Choice 1. What are her preferences in Choice 2? As the two choices are identical in terms of probabilities and final payoff, her preferences are the same, that is, D is preferred to C. Now consider Ola, who behaves in accordance with prospect theory with decision weights ( p) p and value function x for x 0 vx ( ) 2x for x 0

b) What are Ola s preferences in the two choices? In Kahneman and Tversky s paper on prospect theory, similar choices are presented and they are interpreted as if the money initially given/taken are pocketed and the lotteries are considered with reference point zero irrespective of what they are given or have to pay. Given this assumption and the value function, v(-500)=-1000, so the value of the two alternatives are A: 2*(-500)*50%+500*50% = -250, B 2*(-100)*100% = -200. Thus Ola prefers B to A (just like Ann) In the second choice the similar calculation yields: C: 1000*50% + 0*50% = 500 D: = 400 so Ola prefers C to D, unlike Ann. Reference points are not very precisely defined in prospect theory. In Kahneman and Tversky (1979) only positive amounts are given upfront. An alternative reference point is possible in the second choice, arguing that the person is in the loss after paying 100 Kroner. The calculation would then be C: 900*50% + 2*(-100)*50% = 350 D: 300*100% = 300 Ola still prefers C. If the ambiguity of reference points is discussed that is extra good. The latter choice with no discussion seems less natural than the first. Problem 3 (counts 35%) Present-biasedness is one way of representing a person with self-control problems. A particular way of modeling such present-biasedness is to assume that she has (, )-preferences. (a) Explain what is meant by (, )-preferences, and how it departs from intertemporal preferences with exponential discounting. Why does (, )-preferences lead to problems of time-inconsistency? (b) Explain what is meant by naïve and sophisticated behavior when preferences are timeinconsistent. Explain why a sophisticated person with (, )-preferences may be willing to pay for restricting future choices or changing future relative prices, while a naïve person with (, )-preferences will not.

Consider the problem of choosing a membership plan for a health club. Each visit to the health club generates a future benefit, but carries an immediate cost. The health club offers a choice between either paying a monthly membership fee allowing free usage or paying a per-visit price. (c) Explain why a naïve person with (, )-preferences may accept paying the monthly membership fee, even though the average cost per actual visit turns out to exceed the pervisit price. (d) Explain why also a sophisticated person with (, )-preferences may accept paying the monthly membership fee, even though the average cost per actual visit turns out to exceed the per-visit price. The dual-self model, in which a long-term planner attempts to control at a cost a series of short-term doers, is an alternative way of representing a person with self-control problems. (e) Will a person that makes decisions as modeled by the dual-self model accept paying the monthly membership fee, even though the average cost per actual visit turns out to exceed the per-visit price? (f) Observed behavior shows that consumers accept paying the monthly membership fee, even though the average cost per actual visit turns out to exceed the per-visit price. However, some consumers continue to pay the membership fee for several months after their last actual visit to the health club. Are any of the models above (present-biasedness with naïve behavior, present-biasedness with sophisticated behavior, a long-term planner controlling a series of short-term doers) consistent with such behavior? Problem 4 (counts 35 %) (a) What is a convention? Explain. Give at least one example, and explain why you believe the example fits your definition. A convention is, roughly, a rule of behavior that everyone is expected to follow, everyone knows that everyone is expected to follow it, and the behavior constitutes a Nash equilibrium. Below are some definitions and explanations, all of them discussed in the course material/seminars/lectures. Young (1998, on the compulsory reading list) writes: [ ] a convention is equilibrium behavior in a game played repeatedly by many different individuals in society, where the behaviors are widely known to be customary. Note the importance of knowledge: the behaviors must not only be customary, they must be known to be customary, or else the behaviors are not in fact self-enforcing. In the same author s The Economics of Convention (Journal of Economic Perspectives 10(2), 105-122, 1996) he elaborates (p. 105): By a convention, we mean a pattern of behavior that is customary, expected and self-enforcing. Everyone conforms, everyone expects others to conform, and everyone has good reason to conform because conforming is in each person's best interest when everyone else plans to conform (Lewis, 1969). Familiar examples include following rules of the road, adhering to conventional codes of dress and using words with their conventional meanings. [ ] The main feature of a convention is that, out of a host of conceivable choices, only one is actually used. This fact also explains why conventions are needed: they resolve problems of indeterminacy in

interactions that have multiple equilibria. Indeed, from a formal point of view, we may define a convention as an equilibrium that everyone expects in interactions that have more than one equilibrium. (b) What is the difference between a convention and a social norm? Discuss. Do you think the example of a convention you provided in 3a) could be considered a social norm? Why/why not? Several definitions of social norms exist in the economics literature, and their exact meaning does not necessarily coincide. Further, sociologists and psychologists often use the concept in different ways than economists. Thus, students should be given some flexibility in how to respond, but they need to demonstrate that they are familiar with the definitions and applications used in the course. In the lectures, I have defined a social norm as follows: A social norm is a rule of behavior that one is expected to follow, and which is enforced through social sanctions (others approval and/or disapproval). The question asks for a discussion, not simply a correct answer, since both convention and social norm can be defined in many (slightly) different ways. The difference emphasized in class is that a social norm is enforced through social sanctions. This is not necessarily the case for a convention (so in this sense, a convention is a wider concept than a social norm ). For example, driving on the right side of the road (in Norway) is a rule of behavior which would be self-enforcing even in the absence of social (or legal) sanctions. For something to be a social norm and not only a convention, according to this criterion, the social sanctions should be required to make the behavior required by the norm self-enforcing. The definition of a social norm I used in class does not specify that the social norm represents equilibrium behavior. However, the examples of social norms discussed formally in class all implied that this was the case, so a social norm constituting equilibrium behavior has been an implicit assumption in the discussion in class. Consider a large society with N members. Let H be the quality of society s health care system, which is a public good. Assume that H is determined by where j = 1,, N, and t j is person j s tax payment. N H = t j Assume that for every tax payer i there are only two alternatives for tax payment: Either t i =1 (i is a tax payer), or t i = 0 (i is a tax evader). The tax authorities in this society are unable to verify whether a given individual has paid her taxes, and consequently, tax evaders need not fear legal punishment. Every member of society has an identical exogenous income, Y. Person i s budget constraint is given by j=1 x i + t i where x i denotes person i s consumption of private goods.

Assume that the behavior of Anna, a member of this society, is determined by maximization of the following utility function: U A = u(x A ) + v(h) where U A is Anna s utility, and u and v are increasing and concave functions. (c) Discuss whether you find it reasonable to call Anna an altruist. There are at least two interpretations of Anna s utility function: i) She can be a Homo Oeconomicus ( selfish ), and v( ) reflects that she cares about her own access to the public good; ii) She can be what Andreoni (1988) called a pure altruist, where v( ) reflects than she cares about others access to the public good. (Namedropping of Andreoni not required.) (Of course it is possible to interpret v(h) as representing a preference for both one s own and others access to H. I would consider this a variety of pure altruism.) (d) Assume that Anna does not think her behavior will influence the behavior of others. Demonstrate under what conditions Anna will choose to pay her tax, and provide an intuitive explanation for your result. Anna maximizes her utility. Since only two alternatives are available, t i = 0 and t i = 1, there is no point in differentiating the utility function, one must compare utility in the two alternatives. Let H -i denote the level of H provided by others than i. This will be exogenous to i. If i does not pay her taxes, t i =0, then U i = u(y) + v(h -i ). If she does pay, i.e. t i =1, U i = u(y-1) + v(h -i +1). Hence i will pay her tax if u(y-1) + v(h -i +1) u(y) + v(h -i ) (equality implies indifference; with the assumption made, we cannot know what i will do in that case). This can be rewritten as v(h -i +1) - v(h -i ) u(y) - u(y-1), which says that the gain to i in terms of increased public good supply (whether these gains are altruistically motivated or not) must be larger than her loss in terms of lost consumption benefits. Since v is an increasing and concave function, the gain v(h -i +1) - v(h -i ) is higher the lower H -i. Hence, one way to interpret this is that i will only contribute if others contributions are sufficiently low. Consider the same society as described above, but assume now (contrary to the assumption made about Anna above) that every member i of society maximizes a utility function of the following type: U i = u(x i ) + v(h) + s i where U i is i s utility, u and v are increasing and concave functions, and s i is social approval to i from others. Social approval to i is given by s i = t i Ka

where K>0, and a = the share of tax payers in society, where 0 a 1. Assume that every i considers others behavior as exogenous (not affected by i s choices). Under what conditions will everyone in this society pay their taxes, even though there is no legal punishment for tax evasion? For each i, paying taxes is now optimal if u(y-1) + v(h -i +1)+ Ka u(y) + v(h -i ), or (*) a [u(y) - u(y-1) + v(h -i ) - v(h -i +1)]/K. That is, paying tax is individually optimal if a, the share of tax payers, is sufficiently large. If everyone pays their tax, a=1. Is it then individually optimal to pay one s tax, or to deviate and not pay? With a=1, (*) becomes (**) 1 [u(y) - u(y-1) + v(h -i ) - v(h -i +1)]/K. If this condition holds, t i =1 for all is a Nash equilibrium. However, although the above is a necessary condition for this to be a NE, it may not be the only NE. Consequently, even if condition (**) holds, the economy is not necessarily in the state where everyone pays their taxes. Assume that no-one pays their taxes, i.e. a=0. Is it then individually optimal to pay? (*) then becomes 0 [u(y) - u(y-1) + v(h -i ) - v(h -i +1)]/K, or v(h -i +1) - v(h -i ) u(y-1) -u(y) which is exactly the same condition derived above for Anna to prefer paying her tax. If this condition is not fulfilled, i will follow others and not pay her tax. That is, unless it would be optimal to pay one s tax even in the absence of the preference for social approval, t i =0 for all is also a Nash equilibrium. There will also be a NE in which (*) holds with equality, corresponding to a mixed strategy equilibrium, in which everyone is indifferent between paying and not paying tax. Hence, for everyone in this society pay their tax, (**) must hold, and if there are several Nash equilibria the economy must be in the tax-paying equilibrium, not one of the others.