Notes for Section: Week 4

Similar documents
Notes for Section: Week 7

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Answers to Problem Set 4

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

Economics 171: Final Exam

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information

LECTURE NOTES ON GAME THEORY. Player 2 Cooperate Defect Cooperate (10,10) (-1,11) Defect (11,-1) (0,0)

Introduction to Game Theory

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

Economics 51: Game Theory

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

Sequential Rationality and Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Economics 335 March 2, 1999 Notes 6: Game Theory

Rationalizable Strategies

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

1 Solutions to Homework 3

Follow the Leader I has three pure strategy Nash equilibria of which only one is reasonable.

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Dynamic Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Dynamic Games 1 / 18

ECO 5341 (Section 2) Spring 2016 Midterm March 24th 2016 Total Points: 100

Microeconomics III Final Exam SOLUTIONS 3/17/11. Muhamet Yildiz

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally.

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Chapter 11: Dynamic Games and First and Second Movers

The Nash equilibrium of the stage game is (D, R), giving payoffs (0, 0). Consider the trigger strategies:

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

GAME THEORY: DYNAMIC. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Frank Cowell: Dynamic Game Theory

HW Consider the following game:

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

M.Phil. Game theory: Problem set II. These problems are designed for discussions in the classes of Week 8 of Michaelmas term. 1

Economics 502 April 3, 2008

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

Simon Fraser University Fall Econ 302 D200 Final Exam Solution Instructor: Songzi Du Wednesday December 16, 2015, 8:30 11:30 AM

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

Problem Set 2 - SOLUTIONS

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

Exercise Chapter 10

Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ

CHAPTER 15 Sequential rationality 1-1

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30)

Advanced Micro 1 Lecture 14: Dynamic Games Equilibrium Concepts

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

Microeconomic Theory August 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

(a) (5 points) Suppose p = 1. Calculate all the Nash Equilibria of the game. Do/es the equilibrium/a that you have found maximize social utility?

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Francesco Nava Microeconomic Principles II EC202 Lent Term 2010

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

An introduction on game theory for wireless networking [1]

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

Chapter 8. Repeated Games. Strategies and payoffs for games played twice

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Mixed Strategies. Samuel Alizon and Daniel Cownden February 4, 2009

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Credibility and Subgame Perfect Equilibrium

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 19 May, 2008.

REPEATED GAMES. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Frank Cowell: Repeated Games. Almost essential Game Theory: Dynamic.

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

Game Theory. Important Instructions

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Transcription:

Economics 160 Professor Steven Tadelis Stanford University Spring Quarter, 2004 Notes for Section: Week 4 Notes prepared by Paul Riskind (pnr@stanford.edu). spot errors or have questions about these notes. Let me know if you 1 Proofs About Nash Equilibria In this class, you will often have to prove that all Nash equilibria for a game have a particular characteristic. Problem set 3 required you to complete several such proofs. A useful technique for proving such statements is the proof by contradiction. Recall that in a proof by contradiction, you assume the opposite of what you want to prove, and then show that the assumption leads to an impossibility. To prove by contradiction that the Nash equilibria of a game have a particular characteristic, do the following: 1. Assume that the equilibria do not have the characteristic in question. 2. Show that if the equilibria do not have the characteristic, then some player can profitably deviate from her strategy to another with a higher payoff. 3. Conclude that because some player can profitably deviate from her strategy, she s not playing a best response, and that therefore the strategy profile cannot be a Nash equilibrium. It follows that all equilibria must have the characteristic. 2 Using Subgame Perfect Equilibrium to Analyze the Credibility of Threats and Promises An easy application of subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE) is to study the credibility of threats and promises. A threat or promise is credible if you have an incentive to carry it out after the party to whom you ve made your threat or promise acts. 1

2.1 Example 1: Predatory Pricing The market for dog biscuits has two firms. Call one firm the predator (P ), and call the other firm the rival (R). The predator is considering whether to engage in predatory pricing the practice of pricing below cost to inflict losses on a rival and drive her out of the market in the hope of reaping monopoly profits later. The rival first decides whether to stay in the market (S) orexitthemarket (E). The predator observes the rival s decision and then either engages in predatory pricing against the rival (P ) or doesn t engage in predatory pricing (D). If the rival exits the market, the predator gains a monopoly and earns 1000, while the rival gets 0. If the rival stays in the market, the firms share the market and each earns a profit of 300. Predatory pricing costs each firm 400, however, so if the rival stays in the market for dog biscuits (S) and the predator engages in predatory pricing (P ), each earns a total of -100. In the following gametree,thepredator spayoff appears on top: R E S 1000 0 P P D -100-100 300 300 Let s identify all NE and SPE for this game. We ll ignore mixed strategies. We ll first identify all NE by converting this game to normal form. The 2

payoff matrix is: Rival E S Predator P 1000, 0 100, 100 D 1000, 0 300, 300 We ll again use the method of drawing a line below a set of payoffs when the predator is playing a best response and a line above a set of payoffs when the rival is playing a best response. Clearly, the game has two NE in pure strategies: (P, E) and (D, S). Now, let s identify the SPE for this game using the extensive form. This game has perfect information (all information sets are singletons), so we can use backward induction. Start with the predator s decision. If the rival stays in the market (S), the predator is strictly better off not engaging in predatory pricing (D), so she ll choose D. Now look at the rival s decision. Anticipating that the predator won t prey on her, the rival will stay in the market (S) so she can earn 300 rather than 0. Thus, the only strategy profile consistent with backward induction, and thus the only SPE, is (D, S). Why isn t (P, E) a SPE? In this strategy profile, the predator threatens to engage in predatory pricing if the rival stays in the market, and the rival heeds her threat and exits the market. It isn t sequentially rational for the predator to carry out her threat, however: If the rival stays in the market, the predator earns a higher payoff from not preying (D). The predator s threat isn t credible because she has no incentive to carry it out. 3

2.2 Example 2: Predatory Pricing With Credit Constraints In a slightly different game, however, the threat to engage in predatory pricing can be credible. Suppose that the two firms play the same game as before, but that this time, the rival has limited ability to borrow while it loses money. Assume that if the rival ever loses money, it must go bankrupt and leave the industry. Accordingly, if the predator engages in predatory pricing, it bankrupts the rival, ensuring that the predator will have a monopoly in the market for dog biscuits in the future. So now, if the predator preys upon the rival, both firms lose 400 during the period of predatory pricing, but afterwards, the predator gains the monopoly profit of 1000 and the rival gets 0 since she s out of the market. Thus, the predator s total payoff if the rival stays in the market and the predator preys is 1000-400 = 600, and the rival s payoff is 0-400 = -400. Thenewgametreeis: R E S 1000 0 P P D 600-400 300 300 4

Let s again find the NE and SPE for this game. The payoff matrix is: Rival E S Predator P 1000, 0 600, 400 D 1000, 0 300, 300 Now, the only NE is (P, E), and it s easy to show that this strategy profile is also the only SPE. In the subgame beginning with the predator s decision, the Nash equilibrium is for the predator to drive the rival out of the market with predatory pricing. Anticipating that the predator will make good on her threat, the prey will now exit the market without a fight. The difference between this game and the previous game is that in this game, it s actually profitable for the predator to follow through on her threat because she gains a monopoly when the rival goes bankrupt. So in this game, predatory pricing is a credible threat. The beauty of this credible threat is that because the threat is credible, the predator never has to use it! The bottom line: In dynamic games, players playing a NE can make threats or promises that are not credible, in the sense that players would not have incentives to carry out their threats or promises if necessary. This attribute is a clear defect of NE as a solution concept. SPE rules out threats and promises that aren t credible with its requirement that players choose actions that are sequentially rational at every node, even nodes that are not reached in equilibrium. 5

3 Complication #1: Subgames With Multiple Nash Equilibria The following example illustrates how to analyze a dynamic game that has multiple equilibria in one of its subgames. This sort of complication could easily arise in an exam or problem set. Consider the following game in extensive form: 1 L R 2 3 0 X Y 1 1 T B T B 3 3 6 2 2 6 1 1 First, let s identify all proper subgames of this game. Recall that a proper subgame is a set of nodes and corresponding payoffs satisfying two conditions: 6

1. A proper subgame must contain a single root node and all its successors. 2. A proper subgame must contain all nodes in a particular information set if it contains any node belonging to the information set. This game has two proper subgames. The first subgame is the subgame beginning with player 1 s choice between T and B. The second subgame is the entire game. Let s again ignore mixed strategies and find all NE and SPE in pure strategies for this game. We first find all NE by writing out the game in normal form: Player 2 X Y LT 3, 0 3, 0 Player 1 LB 3, 0 3, 0 RT 3, 3 2, 6 RB 6, 2 1, 1 We can quickly identify three NE in pure strategies: (LT, Y ), (LB, Y ), and (RB, X). Next, let s find all the SPE of this game. We can t apply backward induction to this game because it is not a game of perfect information not all information sets consist of single nodes. Instead, we must use the definition of a SPE it induces a NE in every proper subgame and identify the NE for every subgame. The first subgame, beginning at player 1 s choice between T and B, isa2x2 game with simultaneous moves: Player 2 X Y Player 1 T 3, 3 2, 6 B 6, 2 1, 1 This subgame has two NE in pure strategies: (T,Y ) and (B,X). Thus, in a SPE for the entire game, the only possible pairs of actions in this subgame are (T,Y ) and (B,X). Now consider the second subgame, which is the entire game. Player 1 chooses between L and R anticipating that if she chooses R, either(t,y ) or (B,X) will follow. If player 1 expects player 2 to play Y,thenplayer1 will choose L, sincel gives her 3 rather than 2. If player 1 expects player 2 to play X, thenplayer1 will choose R, sincer gives her 6 rather than 3. Thus, the only possible NE for this subgame are (LT, Y ) and (RB, X). We ve shown that (LT, Y ) and (RB, X) induce NE in both proper subgames, so we ve shown that the only two SPE for the entire game are (LT, Y ) and (RB, X). (LB, Y ) is a NE but not a SPE. Neither player is playing a best response in the subgame with simultaneous moves. Notice that one of the two SPE, (LT, Y ), is Pareto inferior to the other, (RB, X). Bothplayerswouldratherplay(RB, X). The Pareto inferior SPE, (LT, Y ), results from player 1 s expectation that player 2 would insist upon the equilibrium more favorable to 2 in the subgame with simultaneous moves. Player 1 therefore chooses L to avoid this subgame and obtain a higher payoff. 7

The bottom line: When a subgame has multiple NE, you must check for SPE inducing each of the possible NE in the subgame. 4 Complication #2: Subgames With Nash Equilibria in Mixed Strategies Let s reexamine the previous example, but this time allow the players to play mixed strategies in the subgame with simultaneous moves. (We could allow the players to play any mixed strategies, but the analysis would quickly get tedious.) Again, this complication has appeared on previous exams. We ll now check whether allowing mixed strategies in the subgame with simultaneous moves changes the set of NE for this game. We re now allowing player 1 to mix between actions T and B, and we re allowing 2 to mix between X and Y. Since player 1 can mix between actions T and B, shecanmix between strategies LT and LB, orbetweenrt and RB. Recall that a player only plays a mixed strategy in Nash equilibrium when she s indifferent toward the strategies she plays with positive probability and (weakly) prefers these strategies to any she does not play with positive probability. Accordingly, we must check whether player 1 can play a mixed strategy that makes player 2 indifferent toward her strategies and whether 2 can make 1 indifferent toward either LT and LB, orrt and RB. As usual, denote mixed strategies by vectors of probabilities assigned to pure strategies. We quickly see that there are two ways that player 1 can make player 2 indifferent. If player 1 plays any mix of LT and LB, thenplayer2 will receive thesameexpectedpayoff (0) from X and Y. Player 1 can also make player 2 indifferent by playing the mixed strategy σ 1 =(0, 0, 0.25, 0.75), whichgives player 2 apayoff of 2.25 from both her pure strategies. Now we ll see whether player 2 has a mixed strategy that will make player 1 willing to mix. If player 2 plays σ 2 =(0.25, 0.75), then1 will be indifferent between RT and RB, since both will yield a payoff of 2.25. 1 won t be willing to mix between RT and RB in equilibrium, however, because she gets a higher payoff (3) from either LT or LB. Any mixed strategy of player 2 makes player 1 indifferent between LT and LB, but we need to make sure that 1 does not prefer RT or RB to LT and LB when 2 plays her mixed strategy. If 2 plays σ 2 =(q, 1 q) with q [0, 1], thenplayer1 s payoffs from her pure strategies are: u 1 (LT ) = u 1 (LB) =3 u 1 (RT ) = 3q +2(1 q) =2+q u 1 (RB) = 6q +(1 q) =1+5q Player 1 will never strictly prefer RT toamixoflt and LB, since q [0, 1], u 1 (RT )=2+q 3=u 1 (LT )=u 1 (LB). Player 1 will strictly prefer RB to 8

amixoflt and LB, however,ifu 1 (RB) =1+5q>3, which happens when q>0.4. So player 1 will only mix between LT and LB when 2 plays the mixed strategy σ 2 =(q, 1 q) with q [0, 0.4]. We conclude that allowing the players to use mixed strategies in the subgame with simultaneous moves creates a continuum of new Nash equilibria of the form σ 1 =(p, 1 p, 0, 0), σ 2 =(q, 1 q) with p [0, 1], andq [0, 0.4]. We now check whether allowing mixed strategies changes the set of SPE. First, observe that allowing mixed strategies in the subgame with simultaneous moves gives this subgame a new NE. The players are both indifferent between their pure actions if and only if they play the profile of mixed actions bσ 1 =(0.25, 0.75) and bσ 2 =(0.25, 0.75). (Recall that we solve for equilibria in mixed strategies by first finding the set of mixed strategies for player i that make player j indifferent toward some of his pure strategies and then find the set of mixed strategies for j that make i indifferent toward some of his pure strategies.) If they play these mixed actions, then both players receive payoffs of 2.25 from each of their two pure actions, so both are indifferent and therefore willing to mix in equilibrium. This subgame has no other equilibria in mixed strategies. Second, observe that if the players play bσ 1 =(0.25, 0.75) and bσ 2 =(0.25, 0.75) in the subgame with simultaneous moves, then player 1 will choose L, giving her a payoff of 3 rather than the payoff of 2.25 from choosing R. Thus, allowing mixed strategies in the subgame with simultaneous moves creates only 1 new SPE: eσ 1 =(0.25, 0.75, 0, 0), andeσ 2 =(0.25, 0.75). (Youshouldbeable to express these mixed strategies as behavioral strategies!) All the other new NE are not SPE, because in these other new NE the players do not play best responses in the subgame with simultaneous moves. Bottom line: Watch out for equilibria in mixed strategies even in dynamic games, and look for SPE in which players mix in some subgames. 5 Complication #3: Continuous Action Spaces So far, we ve only analyzed examples in which the players had finite sets of actions at each information set. You should also, however, be prepared to solve problems in which the players have infinite sets of actions at some information sets. You and your dog own the only two firms in the dog biscuit industry. Dog biscuits are differentiated products. You and your dog compete by choosing prices. Let p Y be your price, and let your dog s price be p D. Your demand is D Y (p Y,p D )=A αp Y + βp D, and your dog s demand is D D (p D,p Y )= A αp D + βp Y. Notice that each firm s demand decreases with its own price and increases with its rival s price. Assume α>β>0, sothateachfirm s demand is more sensitive to its own price than to its rival s price. To keep the analysis simple, also assume that the firms only choose prices for which the 9

preceding expressions give non-negative demands. Assume both firms have zero costs, so the profit functions are: π Y (p Y,p D ) = p Y D Y (p Y,p D )=p Y (A αp Y + βp D ) π D (p D,p Y ) = p D D D (p D,p Y )=p D (A αp D + βp Y ) Throughout this problem, ignore mixed strategies. First, suppose you and your dog choose prices simultaneously. We find the best response functions by maximizing each firm s profit with respect to its own price, taking the other firm s price as given. The first order conditions are: π Y (p Y,p D ) p Y = A p Y + βp D =0 π D (p D,p Y ) p D = A p D + βp Y =0 (Throughout this example, second order conditions are satisfied because each firm s profit functionisconcaveinitsownprice.) Thebestresponsefunctions are: BR Y (p D ) = A + βp D BR D (p Y ) = A + βp Y In Nash equilibrium, both firms play best responses, so we solve the pair of equations p Y = BR Y (p D ) and p D = BR D (p Y ) to obtain p Y = p D = A β. This pair of prices is the unique Nash equilibrium. Now, suppose that you choose your price first, and then your dog chooses his price after observing your price. Let s find all the SPE in pure strategies. We ll also note the possibility of NE that are not SPE. Before we begin, ask yourself how many proper subgames this game has. Since a unique subgame follows every possible choice of price you can make, and since you can choose from infinitely many possible prices, there must be infinitely many proper subgames. Now ask yourself how many proper subgames the game had when you and your dog chose prices simultaneously. Since neither player knew the other s price, there was only one subgame the game as a whole. We conclude that a game with continuous strategy sets will often, but not always, have infinitely many proper subgames. Observe that this game has perfect information: All information sets consist of single nodes. We can therefore identify all SPE using backward induction. Your dog chooses his optimal price after observing your price. Given your price, his best response function provides his unique profit-maximizing price. He therefore sets p D = BR D (p Y )= A+βp Y. WehavefoundtheonlyNEofthe subgames beginning with your dog s choice of price. 10

We now look for NE of the only other subgame the game as a whole that induce NE in the subgames beginning with your dog s choice. Since we must have NE in the subgames beginning with your dog s choice, we know that you anticipate he ll choose p D = A+βpY. You therefore solve: maxπ Y (p Y,BR D (p Y )) = π Y (p Y, A + βp Y )=p Y (A αp Y + β( A + βp Y )) p Y Your first order condition is: A(1 + β β2 ) 2(α )p Y =0 You therefore choose p Y = A(+β). WehavenowfoundtheonlyNEinthe 4α 2 2β 2 game as a whole that induces a NE in every subgame i.e. the only SPE. It is: p Y = A( + β) 4α 2 2β 2 p D (p Y ) = A + βp Y With a bit more algebra, you can show that you choose a higher price in this game than in the game in which you and your dog choose prices simultaneously. Since you choose a higher price in this game, and your dog s best response function increases with your price, your dog also chooses a higher price. In effect, you commit to a high price by moving first, and your dog, secure in the knowledge that your price will be high, also chooses a high price. With still more algebra, we can show that your profit is lower than your dog s profit, so unlike in the sequential Cournot game, moving first in this game is a disadvantage. Nonetheless, both players are strictly better off in the sequential game than in the game with simultaneous moves! Here s a numerical example to illustrate these points. Assume the following parameter values: A = 30 α = 2 β = 1 In the pricing game with simultaneous moves, the outcome is: p Y = p D =10 q Y = q D =20 π Y = π D = 200 11

In the sequential pricing game in which you move first, the outcome is: p Y = 10.71 p D = 10.18 q Y = 18.83 q D = 20.35 π Y = 201.67 π D = 207.16 12