Econ 711 Homework 1 Solutions

Similar documents
CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications Final Exam Ronaldo Carpio Jan. 13, 2015

(a) (5 points) Suppose p = 1. Calculate all the Nash Equilibria of the game. Do/es the equilibrium/a that you have found maximize social utility?

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Econ 711 Final Solutions

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395

Lecture 6 Dynamic games with imperfect information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Second Midterm Examination Answers

The Ohio State University Department of Economics Econ 601 Prof. James Peck Extra Practice Problems Answers (for final)

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 9

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

Answers to Problem Set 4

Econ 414 Midterm Exam

Dynamic Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Dynamic Games 1 / 18

Answer Key: Problem Set 4

Notes for Section: Week 4

AS/ECON 2350 S2 N Answers to Mid term Exam July time : 1 hour. Do all 4 questions. All count equally.

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

HW Consider the following game:

Duopoly models Multistage games with observed actions Subgame perfect equilibrium Extensive form of a game Two-stage prisoner s dilemma

Economics 171: Final Exam

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

1 Solutions to Homework 3

Game Theory: Additional Exercises

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

Simon Fraser University Fall Econ 302 D200 Final Exam Solution Instructor: Songzi Du Wednesday December 16, 2015, 8:30 11:30 AM

Not 0,4 2,1. i. Show there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player A chooses to play, player A chooses L, and player B chooses L.

Exercise Chapter 10

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

Agenda. Game Theory Matrix Form of a Game Dominant Strategy and Dominated Strategy Nash Equilibrium Game Trees Subgame Perfection

Simon Fraser University Spring 2014

Economics 109 Practice Problems 1, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002

Name. Answers Discussion Final Exam, Econ 171, March, 2012

Econ 302 Assignment 3 Solution. a 2bQ c = 0, which is the monopolist s optimal quantity; the associated price is. P (Q) = a b

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

ECO 5341 (Section 2) Spring 2016 Midterm March 24th 2016 Total Points: 100

Extensive-Form Games with Imperfect Information

Problem Set 2 Answers

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Final Examination December 14, Economics 5010 AF3.0 : Applied Microeconomics. time=2.5 hours

The Nash equilibrium of the stage game is (D, R), giving payoffs (0, 0). Consider the trigger strategies:

Introduction to Game Theory

Université du Maine Théorie des Jeux Yves Zenou Correction de l examen du 16 décembre 2013 (1 heure 30)

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

Player 2 H T T -1,1 1, -1

In reality; some cases of prisoner s dilemma end in cooperation. Game Theory Dr. F. Fatemi Page 219

LECTURE NOTES ON GAME THEORY. Player 2 Cooperate Defect Cooperate (10,10) (-1,11) Defect (11,-1) (0,0)

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

Chapter 11: Dynamic Games and First and Second Movers

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Sequential-move games with Nature s moves.

Games of Incomplete Information ( 資訊不全賽局 ) Games of Incomplete Information

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 24, In practice, firms often price their products by marking up a fixed percentage over (average)

CSE 316A: Homework 5

Notes for Section: Week 7

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

Economics 431 Infinitely repeated games

Microeconomic Theory II Spring 2016 Final Exam Solutions

Noncooperative Oligopoly

MKTG 555: Marketing Models

Economic Management Strategy: Hwrk 1. 1 Simultaneous-Move Game Theory Questions.

Game Theory Problem Set 4 Solutions

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 4

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

MIDTERM 1 SOLUTIONS 10/16/2008

Math 135: Answers to Practice Problems

MATH 4321 Game Theory Solution to Homework Two

Francesco Nava Microeconomic Principles II EC202 Lent Term 2010

Answers to Odd-Numbered Problems, 4th Edition of Games and Information, Rasmusen

HE+ Economics Nash Equilibrium

In Class Exercises. Problem 1

Name. FINAL EXAM, Econ 171, March, 2015

Prisoner s dilemma with T = 1

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Strategic Pre-Commitment

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

Today. Applications of NE and SPNE Auctions English Auction Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction

is the best response of firm 1 to the quantity chosen by firm 2. Firm 2 s problem: Max Π 2 = q 2 (a b(q 1 + q 2 )) cq 2

When one firm considers changing its price or output level, it must make assumptions about the reactions of its rivals.

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2 ANSWER KEY

Advanced Microeconomics

EconS 424 Strategy and Game Theory. Homework #5 Answer Key

Mohammad Hossein Manshaei 1394

1 x i c i if x 1 +x 2 > 0 u i (x 1,x 2 ) = 0 if x 1 +x 2 = 0

Dynamic games with incomplete information

EconS 424 Strategy and Game Theory. Homework #5 Answer Key

Transcription:

Econ 711 Homework 1 s January 4, 014 1. 1 Symmetric, not complete, not transitive. Not a game tree. Asymmetric, not complete, transitive. Game tree. 1

Asymmetric, not complete, transitive. Not a game tree. (both and preceed 4, but neither preceeds the other). 4 Asymmetric, not complete, not transitive. Not a game tree. 5 Asymmetric, not complete, vacuously transitive. Not a game tree 1 and both preceed 4, but neither preceeds the other.. 1) WTS Defn 1 Defn and ) Defn Defn 1 1) Suppose Prop A and not Prop B. There are two possibilities: a) no sequence exists or b) two or more sequences exist. First, we ll consider a): t k t by assumption. Then i, j, t i t and t j t implies t i t j or t j t i by Prop A. Asymmetry implies only one of those can hold, and adding transitivity implies there can be no cycles. Thus we can construct a sequence as in Defn. Now let s consider b): Suppose we can order these nodes two different ways. It must be the case, then, that at least one pair of nodes in the set of preceeding nodes switches order between the two sequences, and thus by transitivity that each node in this pair preceeds the other, violating asymmetry. Contradiction. ) Suppose Prop B holds and we have (t,t,t ) such that t t and t t. Prop B tells us that, since t and t preceed t, there is a unique sequence over this set of two nodes. Thus, either t t or t t, proving Prop A.. 1

Yes it is. Alice only moves at one node, so she has perfect information, and Bob always knows what node he is at because he knows how much money Alice has offered him the distinguishing feature between the nodes he plays. For the subgame starting with B 1, Bob is indifferent between accepting and rejecting, so either is valid. For all other subgames, Bob strictly prefers accepting. Thus, for Alice, there are two cases: 1) Bob accepts all. In this case, Alice s best response is to offer nothing, so the SPNE for (Alice,Bob) is (0,aaaaa). ) Bob rejects 0 and accepts all others. Then Alice s best response is to offer 1, the least she can give while ensuring Bob s acceptance. Then the SPNE is (1,raaaa). 4

Now Bob moves before Alice, but Alice doesn t observe Bob, so she only has one information set despite the fact that she has 5 nodes. Thus, in this case, SPNE doesn t impose any additional constraints beyond NE. There are now many equilibria. If Alice plays 0, all s 1 s s s 4 s 5 are best responses for Bob. If Alice plays i > 0, all strategies where s i = accept are best responses for Bob. For Alice s strategy i to be a best response, we must have i = min{j : s j = a, 0}. Thus the set of SPNE is {0,rrrrr} and {i, s 1 s s s 4 s 5 } where i = min{j : s j = a, 0}. 5 4. 1 Since Bob now cares about all possible actions Alice could chose, rather than just one that she s picked, his only two possibilities are raaaa and aaaaa, as in. However, Alice has no weakly dominant strategies, as her best response is contingent on Bob s strategy. Thus there are no equilibria in weakly dominant strategies. Actions: q 1 [0, ], q (q 1 ) [0, ]. Strategies: firm 1: q 1 [0, ], firm : the set of functions q : [0, ] [0, ] For backwards induction equilibria, first we solve the subgame starting at firm s turn, then we solve firm 1 s problem. Given q 1, firm s best response is to maximize Π (q ) = q ( 1 q 1 q ). Computing the FOC gives us 1 q 1 q = 0 or q = 1 q 1. Thus firm s best response is q (q 1 ) = 1 q 1. Consequently, firm 1 must maximize Π 1 (q 1 ) = q 1 ( 1 q 1 1 q 1 ) = q 1 (1/ q 1 /). Computing the FOC gives us 1/ q 1 = 0 or q 1 = 1. Plugging that into q (q 1 ),we have q = 1/4. Thus the equilibrium outcome is Π 1 = 1/(1 1/ 1/4) = 1/8 and Π = 1/4(1 1/ 1/4) = 1/16. The profit from Cournot is 1/(1/)=1/9, so firm 1 is better off and firm is worse off. 4

5 We ll consider 5 first because and 4 are special cases of it. Consider a strategy of q = 1 q1 for firm if q 1 = q 1and q = 1 otherwise. Essentially, we re making deviating from (q1, 1 q 1 ) as costly as possible for firm 1, to give them as strong incentives as we can to produce those quantities. If firm 1 produces anything else, firm will produce a quantity 1, making firm 1 s profit less than or equal to zero. Firm s behavior for contingencies other than q 1 =q 1 seems irrational, and wouldn t survive in a SPNE, but since we only require a Nash Equilibrium it doesn t matter because firm never has to play those irrational moves in the equilibrium. Thus, given that firm 1 s strategy is q 1 =q 1, firm is playing its best response, and so long as firm 1 s profit is nonnegative, playing q 1 is better than the next best response of producing 0 and getting 0 profit. So long as q 1 1, this condition will be satisfied. Thus the range of supportable q 1 s is [0,1] and the range of supportable q s is [0,1/]. Choosing q 1 = 1/ and using the strategies in part 5 gives us the desired equilibrium. 4 5. 1 Choosing q 1 = 1/4 and using the strategies in part 5 gives us the desired equilibrium, as it is the reverse of the SPNE Stackleberg outcome we derived before. u i (x i, x i x i ) = x i ( x i x i ). Notice this has the same functional form as the profit function in the cournot game, with price and quantity replaced with the public and private goods. The best responses are thus the same: x i = x i. Then the equilibrium x is are x i x i = = 1/ + x i /4 and x i = /. & 5

This is equivalent to Stackleberg, which was solved earlier. 4-1 As we saw in the last homework, then the set of possible Nash Equilibria is x such that x 1 x = 1/4. and x i 1. 4- Player 1 s strategies are simply x 1 [0, 1]. Player s strategies are the set of functions x : [0, 1] [0, 1]. 4- First, we ll solve player s problem. Given x 1, u (x, x 1 ) = x + x 1 x F OC : u (x, x 1 ) x = 1 1 x 1 x = 0 x = 7/4 x 1 This is our best response for player. Then player 1 solves u 1 (x 1, x ) = x 1 + 1/4,which has a corner solution of x 1 = 1. Essentially, since expenditures on the public good are the same no matter what player 1 does, since player has an incentive to make up for player 1 s shortchanging, player 1 might as well not contribute anything and leave it all to player to finance the public good. Thus we have a NE of (1, 7/4 x 1 ) and an equilibrium outcome of / for player 1 and 5/4 for player. Note that te SPNE is the element of the set of NE in the simultaneous move game that is most favorable to player 1 and least favorable to player. 6. 1 6

Notice that at the last node of the game tree (the last subgame), stopping is the unique best response. Given that player will stop in the last period, player 1 s best response at the second to last period (the second to last subgame) is to stop. Continuing inductively, we see that, given optimal play in all later periods, the best response at every node is to stop. Thus the only SPNE strategy profile is s 1 s...s 99 s 100 for both players. As in part, the game must stop in the first period. Suppose we had a NE where the first n actions were continue and the n+1th action was stop (any strategy profile with continue as the first move will be of this form, since the game stops after the last period). Then whoever plays at period n will have an incentive to deviate, as stopping n the nth period rather than the n+1th period will net them 1 additional dollar. Then the only possible NE strategy profiles have player 1 stopping in the first period, and player stopping in the second period. However, all other elements of the strategy that is, actions at every node 7

after the second can vary freely, since they are never reached and thus have no effect on the payoffs. Player must play stop at the second period so that player 1 doesn t have an incentive to deviate to continue. Thus the NE strategy profiles are s 1 a...a 99 a 100 for player 1 and s 1 a...a 99 a 100, where a can be either stop or continue. 4 There are no strictly dominated strategies. Every node after the first will never be reached under certain strategies specifically where player 1 stops in the first period, so there are situations where the actions at those nodes don t matter. Thus, we only need consider player 1 s first action. Continue is strictly better if player s first action is continue, and strictly worse otherwise, so there is no action in period 1 that is strictly better for player 1 under all contingencies. 7. 1 8

Strategies for player 1 are of the form a 1 a a a 4...a 8, where a 1 {(A, B), (B, C), (C, D)}and all other actions are chosen from the two options that are being voted for at that node. We end up with 16 information sets because player 1 chooses the first voting pair (1 info set), votes on the first pair ( info sets), and votes on the second pair (*8=4 info sets). Strategies for player are of the form a 1 a a a 4...a 54, where all actions are chosen from the two options that are being voted for at that node. We end up with 54 information sets because player votes on the first pair (*=6 info sets) and votes on the second pair (*8*=48 info sets). Strategies for player are of the form a 1 a a a 4...a 108, where all actions are chosen from the 9

two options that are being voted for at that node. We end up with 108 information sets because player votes on the first pair (*4=1 info sets) and votes on the second pair (*4*8=96 info sets). As you can see in the extensive form of the game tree, the second rounds of voting yield outcome A for (A,B), C for (A,C), and B for (B,C). Then, once we ve finished the first round of voting, we know the payoff, and can plug it in as in the figure. Now we see that, if player 1 chooses (A,C), the voting will proceed to (A,B), which is optimal for player 1. Thus player 1 will choose (A,C) and the final vote will be for A. There are many SPNE strategy profiles there are many information sets where players are indifferent, and each of those doubles the number of SPNE strategy profiles since either choice is consistent with best responding (a quick count gives me ˆ50 strategies, but I m obviously not going to write them out). As before, there are many, many SPNE strategy profiles, and they can be defined analogously to 7., though the reordering of moves will change the number of information sets each player has and the way their strategies must be written down. The set of SPNE outcomes will remain the same, however notice that, in a voting game with options and voters, a given voter is either not pivotal, in which case their vote doesn t matter, or they are pivotal, in which case they choose their most preferred option. Later voters observe the votes of earlier voters, but the only change this can cause in their strategy is to make them vote for a less preferred option if they know their vote isn t pivotal, which only happens in this case if the same outcome obtains regardless of their vote. Thus, changing the order of voting will not change the equilibrium payoffs. 10