Chapter 1. Utility Theory. 1.1 Introduction

Similar documents
Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

ECON 581. Decision making under risk. Instructor: Dmytro Hryshko

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Expected value is basically the average payoff from some sort of lottery, gamble or other situation with a randomly determined outcome.

Utility and Choice Under Uncertainty

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Investment and Portfolio Management. Lecture 1: Managed funds fall into a number of categories that pool investors funds

Choice under Uncertainty

UTILITY ANALYSIS HANDOUTS

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Stat 6863-Handout 1 Economics of Insurance and Risk June 2008, Maurice A. Geraghty

E&G, Chap 10 - Utility Analysis; the Preference Structure, Uncertainty - Developing Indifference Curves in {E(R),σ(R)} Space.

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Economic Risk and Decision Analysis for Oil and Gas Industry CE School of Engineering and Technology Asian Institute of Technology

Financial Economics. A Concise Introduction to Classical and Behavioral Finance Chapter 2. Thorsten Hens and Marc Oliver Rieger

Lecture 11 - Risk Aversion, Expected Utility Theory and Insurance

If U is linear, then U[E(Ỹ )] = E[U(Ỹ )], and one is indifferent between lottery and its expectation. One is called risk neutral.

ECON Financial Economics

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

On the Empirical Relevance of St. Petersburg Lotteries. James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Bodo Vogt

Unit 4.3: Uncertainty

MICROECONOMIC THEROY CONSUMER THEORY

3.1 The Marschak-Machina triangle and risk aversion

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Expected utility theory; Expected Utility Theory; risk aversion and utility functions

Figure 1: Smooth curve of through the six points x = 200, 100, 25, 100, 300 and 600.

Foundations of Financial Economics Choice under uncertainty

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

05/05/2011. Degree of Risk. Degree of Risk. BUSA 4800/4810 May 5, Uncertainty

Time Resolution of the St. Petersburg Paradox: A Rebuttal

Comparison of Payoff Distributions in Terms of Return and Risk

Chapter 18: Risky Choice and Risk

Making Hard Decision. ENCE 627 Decision Analysis for Engineering. Identify the decision situation and understand objectives. Identify alternatives

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance

Models & Decision with Financial Applications Unit 3: Utility Function and Risk Attitude

Advanced Risk Management

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

Topic Four Utility optimization and stochastic dominance for investment decisions. 4.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion

Chapter 6: Risky Securities and Utility Theory

Review Session. Prof. Manuela Pedio Theory of Finance

Lecture 3: Utility-Based Portfolio Choice

ECO 203: Worksheet 4. Question 1. Question 2. (6 marks)

Economic of Uncertainty

Answers to chapter 3 review questions

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

Topic 3 Utility theory and utility maximization for portfolio choices. 3.1 Optimal long-term investment criterion log utility criterion

Economic & Financial Decisions under Risk (Chapters 1&2) Eeckhoudt, Gollier & Schlesinger (Princeton Univ Press 2005)

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

Managerial Economics Uncertainty

Exercises for Chapter 8

SAC 304: Financial Mathematics II

TOPIC: PROBABILITY DISTRIBUTIONS

Problem Set 2. Theory of Banking - Academic Year Maria Bachelet March 2, 2017

We examine the impact of risk aversion on bidding behavior in first-price auctions.

1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance

Discrete gambles: Theoretical study of optimal bet allocations for the expo-power utility gambler

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Financial Economics: Making Choices in Risky Situations

Universal Portfolios

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2014 Answer any 7 of these 8 questions Good luck!

Managerial Economics

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Module 1: Decision Making Under Uncertainty

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

Representing Risk Preferences in Expected Utility Based Decision Models

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2015

Mock Examination 2010

SWITCHING, MEAN-SEEKING, AND RELATIVE RISK

Expected Utility Theory

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Optimizing Portfolios

ECMC49F Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Oct 26, 2005 Duration: 1 hour 50 mins Total Marks: 100. [1] [25 marks] Decision-making under certainty

Lecture 2 Basic Tools for Portfolio Analysis

Economics Homework 5 Fall 2006 Dickert-Conlin / Conlin

Intertemporal Risk Attitude. Lecture 7. Kreps & Porteus Preference for Early or Late Resolution of Risk

Random variables. Discrete random variables. Continuous random variables.

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

NOTES ON ATTITUDE TOWARD RISK TAKING AND THE EXPONENTIAL UTILITY FUNCTION. Craig W. Kirkwood

FINC3017: Investment and Portfolio Management

Microeconomic Theory May 2013 Applied Economics. Ph.D. PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Applied Economics Graduate Program.

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

Attitudes Toward Risk. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/16. (Lecture 11, Micro Theory I)

Principes de choix de portefeuille

Choice Under Uncertainty

Analysing risk preferences among insurance customers

Arbitrage Pricing. What is an Equivalent Martingale Measure, and why should a bookie care? Department of Mathematics University of Texas at Austin

Aversion to Risk and Optimal Portfolio Selection in the Mean- Variance Framework

The St. Petersburg Paradox. Knut K. Aase Sandviken - Bergen, Norway. Sept., Abstract

ECE 302 Spring Ilya Pollak

Insights from Behavioral Economics on Index Insurance

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 3

Problem Set 3 - Solution Hints

Remarks on Probability

Transcription:

Chapter 1 Utility Theory 1.1 Introduction St. Petersburg Paradox (gambling paradox) the birth to the utility function http://policonomics.com/saint-petersburg-paradox/ The St. Petersburg paradox, is a theoretical game used in economics, to represent a classical example were, by taking into account only the expected value as the only decision criterion, the decision maker will be misguided into an irrational decision. This paradox was presented and solved in Daniel Bernoullis Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae (translated as Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk), 1738, hence its name, St. Petersburg. He solved it by making the distinction between expected value and expected utility, as the latter uses weighted utility multiplied by probabilities, instead of using weighted outcomes. However, since then, alternative approaches have been used by different researches to answer this paradox. Suppose there is a fair game with 50/50 chance of winning/losing. The bet is $1 and you can repeatedly bet at any amount. Hence the probability of winning the game is asymptotically 1. And hence the price to pay to enter the game is also infinity. The key of the paradox is to determine the value someone would be willing to pay in order to play a lottery game that works as follows: a fair coin is tossed, if tail appears the player is paid $2 (in case the amount paid to play is $1), if not, the coin is tossed again, until tail appears, doubling the initial gain every time the coin is tossed. For example, for toss number 3 (n = 3 ), the payoff would be 8 (2 n ) and the expected value, which here equals the payoff multiplied by the probability (here, 1).

2 Chapter 1: Utility Theory The probability that the first tail appears in the toss number n is equal to p n = 1/2 n, being 2 n the payoff. Therefore, the expected value for n tosses would be: n=1 p n2 n = n=1 1 = (1.1) If we use the expected value as the decision criterion, the player should be willing to pay $ in order to play. However, no rational individual would accept this. 1.2 Basic Properties/Axioms of Utility Function Behaviors of Human Being Prefer more to less non decreasing utility function Satiability the fact that any single want is satiable leads to the law of diminishing marginal utility Scarcity increasing marginal cost of production 1.3 Risk Aversion 1.3.1 Basics Jensens inequality If G(x) is concave in x, then: The proof of the equality is really simple. E[G(x)] < G(E[x]) (1.2) G(x) = G( x)+g ( x)(x x)+ 1 2 G (x )(x x) 2 (1.3) where x [x, x]. As a result,

Risk Aversion 3 E[G(x)] = G( x)+g ( x)(e[x] x)+ 1 2 G (x )E[(x x) 2 ] = G(E[x])+ 1 2 G (x )E[(x x) 2 ] (1.4) < G(E[x]) because G (x ) < 0 (slope G (x) decreasing) due to a concave function. Risk Adverse Utility For state-independent utility function of wealth (such as W = E[W]+ε), the utility function is risk-averse if U(E[W]) > E[U(W)] U(E[W]) > E[U(W +ε)] (1.5) where E[ε] = 0 [Definition] An individual is risk-averse is defined iff his utility function of wealth is strictly concave at the relevant wealth levels. Consequently, using Jensen s inequality, we have: E[U(W +ε)] < U(E[W +ε]) = U(E[W]) E[U(W)] = U(W) (1.6) [An Example] Consider a simple gamble, { ε = λa (1 λ)a 1 λ λ (1.7) Then, E[ε] = (1 λ)λa λ(1 λ)a = 0 (1.8)

4 Chapter 1: Utility Theory and E[ε 2 ] = (1 λ)λ 2 a 2 +λ(1 λ) 2 a 2 = a 2 λ(1 λ)(λ+(1 λ)) = a 2 λ(1 λ) (1.9) Let W = W +ε and as a result, E[W +ε] = W (1.10) Given that E[W +ε] < U(W), we obtain W < U(W) for all (regardless of) a and λ. Now, assume that there exists a W such that: E[U(W +ε)] = U(W ) (1.11) so that W = W π I represents a certainty equivalent wealth amount to W+ε for theindividualthatmatcheshisexpectedutilityandπ I isthemonetarycompensation of the uncertainty, or known as the risk premium. Or alternatively,, we could define a π C so that: E[U(W +ε+π C )] = U(W) (1.12) where π C represents the compensation to the individual for taking the gamble. 1.3.2 Pratt-Arrow Measure of RA By Taylor s series expansion on the expected utility E[U(W)]: [ E[U(W +ε)] = E U(W)+U (W)ε+ 1 ] 2 U (W)ε 2 +o(ε) U(W)+ 1 2 U (W)E[ε 2 ] (1.13) At the same time, U(W π I ) = U(W)+U (W)( π I )+o(π I ) U(W)+U (W)( π I ) (1.14)

Risk Aversion 5 Hence, 1 2 U (W)σ 2 U (W)( π I ) [ ] π I = U (W) σ 2 U (W) 2 (1.15) and A(W) = U (W) U (W) (1.16) is called the Pratt-Arrow measure of risk aversion. The higher is the risk aversion, the higher is the risk premium π I. We can also have the alternative form: U (W) U (W) = (W) dlnu dw (1.17) [Theorem] If we double-integrate(see proof) the Pratt-Arrow risk aversion, we obtain a linear function in utility. [Proof] Let B = = w Ω w Ω A(w)dw dlnu (w) dw dw = lnu (w)+lnb = ln[u (w)b] (1.18) Then, e B = U b = bu +a (1.19) 1.3.3 Absolute vs. Relative RA 1. da(w) dw > 0 means higher is wealth, higher is π I (compensation for risk or risk premium)

6 Chapter 1: Utility Theory 2. da(w) dw = 0 means risk aversion has nothing to do with amount of wealth 3. da(w) dw < 0 means higher is wealth, lower π I (lower the need for risk compensation) Clearly, (3) is most unreasonable. This is because the marginal utility (of wealth) must be decreasing (axiom). Hence wealth has become less valuable as one becomes richer (has occupied more of it). (2) is also unreasonable because it implies a linear utility function. So only (1) is reasonable. If the absolute risk aversion is diminishing with respect to wealth, then the relative risk aversion R(W) = WA(W) is constant to wealth: dr(w) dw = 0 = A(w)+wdA(w) dw da(w) dw = A(w) w (1.20) which is, we want the absolute risk aversion to be proportional to wealth. 1.3.4 Useful Utility Functions In this section, we demonstrate some useful and popular utility functions. Exponential U(W) = 1 a e aw The absolute and relative risk aversion are: U = e aw U = ae aw A = U U = a R = aw (1.21) This is constant and positive absolute risk aversion (situation 1) which is bad.

Risk Aversion 7 Quadratic U(W) = a(w b) 2 The absolute and relative risk aversion are: U = 2a(W b) U = 2a A = U U = 1 b W R = W b W (1.22) For A to be less than 0, W must be greater than b. So the easiest case is the set b = 0. That is: A = 1 W da dw = 1 W > 0 2 which is not good (higher is wealth, higher is risk aversion). The relative risk aversion is close to constant (under b = 0): R(W) = WA(W) = 1 dr(w) dw = 0 so it does have the desirable relative risk aversion. Log U(W) = a+blnw The two risk aversions are: U = b W U = b W 2 A = U U = 1 W R = 1 (1.23) This is opposite to quadratic utility function. Now both absolute and relative risk aversion is desirable. da(w)/dw < 0 is now negative which is consistent with diminishing risk aversion.

8 Chapter 1: Utility Theory HARA (hyperbolic absolute risk aversion) This is a general utility function that can be made into any of the above special cases: U(W) = 1 r ( ) r aw r 1 r +b (1.24) The two risk aversions are: U = a ( ) r 1 aw 1 r +b ( aw U = a 2 1 r +b A = U U = a ) r 2 ( aw 1 r +b ) 1 (1.25) For r < 1, For r > 1, W A W A The HARA class of utility functions can be made into the following special cases: 1. r = 1, which leads to U = aw +b which is linear 2. r = 2, which leads to U = 1 2 ( aw +b)2 which is quadratic: U = e aw 3. r = (and b = 1) which leads to exponential 4. b = 0 and r < 1 which leads to U = Wr r which is power 5. b = 0 and r = 0 which leads to U = lnw which is log 1.4 Exercises 1. Derive da(w)/dw for the HARA utility function. 2. Draw R(w) (using W as x-axis) with r = 0.5,a = 1,b = 1.