What s wrong with infinity A note on Weitzman s dismal theorem

Similar documents
Characterization of the Optimum

Financial Economics: Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions

Mossin s Theorem for Upper-Limit Insurance Policies

Maximizing the expected net future value as an alternative strategy to gamma discounting

LECTURE 1 : THE INFINITE HORIZON REPRESENTATIVE AGENT. In the IS-LM model consumption is assumed to be a

1 Two Period Exchange Economy

Transport Costs and North-South Trade

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Consumption and Portfolio Choice under Uncertainty

Standard Risk Aversion and Efficient Risk Sharing

Period State of the world: n/a A B n/a A B Endowment ( income, output ) Y 0 Y1 A Y1 B Y0 Y1 A Y1. p A 1+r. 1 0 p B.

Intertemporal choice: Consumption and Savings

1 Consumption and saving under uncertainty

Professor Dr. Holger Strulik Open Economy Macro 1 / 34

CAPITAL BUDGETING IN ARBITRAGE FREE MARKETS

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Expected utility inequalities: theory and applications

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Slides III - Complete Markets

GMM Estimation. 1 Introduction. 2 Consumption-CAPM

The mean-variance portfolio choice framework and its generalizations

Lecture 2 General Equilibrium Models: Finite Period Economies

Large Losses and Equilibrium in Insurance Markets. Lisa L. Posey a. Paul D. Thistle b

RISK POOLING IN THE PRESENCE OF MORAL HAZARD

Micro Theory I Assignment #5 - Answer key

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

16 MAKING SIMPLE DECISIONS

Environmental Protection and Rare Disasters

Chapter 19 Optimal Fiscal Policy

Two Equivalent Conditions

X ln( +1 ) +1 [0 ] Γ( )

Uncertainty and Natural Resources Prudence facing Doomsday

Discounting the Benefits of Climate Change Policies Using Uncertain Rates

Economics 101. Lecture 8 - Intertemporal Choice and Uncertainty

The Aggregation Dilemma. (early draft-no quoting please)

One-Period Valuation Theory

Problem set 1 ECON 4330

1 Asset Pricing: Bonds vs Stocks

Lower Bounds on Revenue of Approximately Optimal Auctions

1 Dynamic programming

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

004: Macroeconomic Theory

Idiosyncratic Risk and Higher-Order Cumulants: A Note

Consumption, Investment and the Fisher Separation Principle

FISCAL FEDERALISM WITH A SINGLE INSTRUMENT TO FINANCE GOVERNMENT. Carlos Maravall Rodríguez 1

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Optimal retention for a stop-loss reinsurance with incomplete information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Social Choice

TAKE-HOME EXAM POINTS)

ECON 6022B Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions Fall 2011

Comment Does the economics of moral hazard need to be revisited? A comment on the paper by John Nyman

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

4 Martingales in Discrete-Time

Using the Maximin Principle

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Fall 2013 D. Romer

Copenhagen Consensus 2008 Perspective Paper. Global Warming

Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes

Consumption and Savings

The Role of Macroeconomics in Evaluating Climate Abatement Policies

Aversion to Risk and Optimal Portfolio Selection in the Mean- Variance Framework

PhD Qualifier Examination

Trade Agreements as Endogenously Incomplete Contracts

Chapter 6. Endogenous Growth I: AK, H, and G

Annuity Markets and Capital Accumulation

Assets with possibly negative dividends

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Introduction to Economics I: Consumer Theory

Andreas Wagener University of Vienna. Abstract

University of Konstanz Department of Economics. Maria Breitwieser.

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Effects of Wealth and Its Distribution on the Moral Hazard Problem

On Diamond-Dybvig (1983): A model of liquidity provision

1 Precautionary Savings: Prudence and Borrowing Constraints

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Answers Econ 8712

Aversion to Risk and Optimal Portfolio Selection in the Mean- Variance Framework

Risk-Taking Behavior with Limited Liability and Risk Aversion

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Radner Equilibrium: Definition and Equivalence with Arrow-Debreu Equilibrium

Workshop on the pricing and hedging of environmental and energy-related financial derivatives

Econ 230B Spring FINAL EXAM: Solutions

PhD Qualifier Examination

market opportunity line fair odds line Example 6.6, p. 120.

Death and Destruction in the Economics of Catastrophes

Chapter 1 Microeconomics of Consumer Theory

Solutions to Problem Set 1

Models and Decision with Financial Applications UNIT 1: Elements of Decision under Uncertainty

Mean Variance Analysis and CAPM

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data

Risk preferences and stochastic dominance

Lecture Notes 1

AK and reduced-form AK models. Consumption taxation.

Problem Set 3. Thomas Philippon. April 19, Human Wealth, Financial Wealth and Consumption

Step 2: Determine the objective and write an expression for it that is linear in the decision variables.

Answers To Chapter 6. Review Questions

Behavioral Competitive Equilibrium and Extreme Prices. Faruk Gul Wolfgang Pesendorfer Tomasz Strzalecki

Stat 6863-Handout 1 Economics of Insurance and Risk June 2008, Maurice A. Geraghty

Consumption and Savings (Continued)

Transcription:

What s wrong with infinity A note on Weitzman s dismal theorem John Horowitz and Andreas Lange Abstract. We discuss the meaning of Weitzman s (2008) dismal theorem. We show that an infinite expected marginal willingness to substitute between today s and future s consumption does not jeopardize cost-benefit-analysis. The optimal level of this willingness to transfer wealth is finite if a safe way of transfering wealth into the future exists. For investments with uncertain returns, we demonstrate that marginal expected rate of substitution is no meaningful indicator for cost-benefit analysis: costbenefit analysis under uncertainty must jointly consider marginal willingness and the options/technologies of transfering income. (JEL: D81, Q54) Keywords: decisions under uncertainty, cost-benefit-analysis, climate policy 1 Introduction In a recent paper, Weitzman (2008) laid out a dismal theorem which states a potential problem for applying cost-benefit analysis (CBA) in the realm of large structural uncertainty. Using the example of climate change, he derives theoretically that the rate at which society would be willing to exchange today s consumption for future s consumption might very well be infinity. The implicit discount factor for consumption might therefore be dominated by such structural uncertainty. In this note, we question the applicability of this theorem for practical cost benefit analysis. More explicitly, we argue that the pure value of infinity does not prevent us from applying CBA in a meaningful way. We show that Weitzman s result applies only to situations in which it is not possible to transfer certain wealth to the future. When such transfers are possible, and because a situation with the ability to transfer is the only economically interesting one, a standard cost-benefit problem arises and an interior solution exists. In the context of climate change, no investment option may exist whose returns are not Correspondence: Andreas Lange, University of Maryland, 2200 Symons Hall, College Park, MD 20742, USA. Email: alange@arec.umd.edu; jhorowitz@arec.umd.edu. 1

subject to climate uncertainty as well. That is, no action we can take may improve, in an absolute sense, our future outcomes should the worst realizations of climate change occur. It is not surprising that cost-benefit analysis should fail in a context where no improvement is possible. However, even if investments are jeopardized in the worst cases, it can be expected that they pay off should climate change turn out to be less severe. When we consider such a situation in which actions that ameliorate climate change are indeed available, the dismal theorem does not apply and the choice of an optimal action is a well-defined, solvable problem. In this case, however, we show that the expected marginal rate of substitution between consumption today and in the future does not represent a meaningful indicator for costbenefit analysis. We demonstrate that a meaningful cost-benefit analysis must jointly consider marginal willingness to substitute between consumption today and tomorrow and the options/technologies of transfering income. In this sense, a separate determination of the benefits from investing and the costs of doing so is impossible. A second part of Weitzman s article, a demonstration that there are fat tails in probabilities of future outcomes, remains valid and indeed skews us toward taking stronger actions that we would under thinner tailed distributions. But this fat tail problem does not preclude a cost-benefit framework. The concept of infinite willingness-to-pay at the margin as suggested by Weitzman should be familiar to the reader: in many theoretical models, Inada conditions are being made in order to avoid corner solutions. In this sense, Weitzman s infinity corresponds to a justification of such Inada-like conditions for the demand of transfers from today to future generations. It shows that the first unit of wealth should be transferred at any cost. Once we have transferred this first unit, however, there is a finite benefit to climate-change control actions that can be weighed against the costs. 2 The basic points Analogously to Weitzman (2008), we consider C as the consumption, with C 0 = 1 denoting the (normalized) present gross consumption. Consumption generates some utility which we 2

assume to be of CRRA (constant relative risk aversion) form U(C) = C1 η 1 η (1) with η > 0. The marginal utility is given by U (C) = C η. Future consumption C 1 is random and depends on a state of nature s S. Differently from Weitzman, we consider investment decisions explicitly. That is, C is not assumed to implicitly include all adaptation and mitgation options. Let p be investment in period 0, yielding net consumption 1 p. Investment generates a future return of R(p, s), yielding net consumption C 1 (s)+r(p, s). For simplicity, we denote R (p, s) = R(p, s)/ p. We assume that R(0, s) = 0. Furthermore, we assume R (p, s)) = R(p, s/ p 2 0 and that R (p, s) R for all p, s. That is, the marginal returns from investment are bounded. This specification explicitly allows that the returns from investment could be zero or even negative in some states of nature. Note, however, that with the choice of the utility function, consumption is normalized to satisfy C 1 (s) + R(p, s) > 0. The standard discounted expected utility in this two-period model from an investment at level p is then given by: U(1 p) + βe[u(c 1 (s) + R(p, s))] (2) where β > 0 denotes the pure rate of time-preference. We first consider a situation in which a technology exists which generates such a safe return to investment, i.e. R(p, s) = ˆR(p) with ˆR (0) > 0. An interior solution to the maximization of (2) then requires: β E[U (C 1 (s) + ˆR(p))] U (1 p) = 1 ˆR (p) (3) Here, the left hand side describes the marginal rate at which the agent would be willing to give up present consumption to obtain one sure unit of consumption in the future while the right hand side gives the marginal costs of doing so. 3

If a corner solution p = 0 were optimal, the first-order condition is 1 β E[U (C 1 (s))] U (1) < 1 ˆR (0) (4) Weitzman demonstrates conditions under which the distribution of C 1 is such that βe[u (C 1 (s))/u (1)] =. From (4), we see however that this cannot correspond to an optimal choice of investment if there exists any technology which transfers a safe asset into the future at finite costs ( ˆR (0) > 0). Instead, we obtain that if there is such a technology, a positive investment 0 < p < 1 implies βe[u (C 1 (s))/u (1)] < 1/ ˆR (0). For any positive R(p) > 0, however, βe[u (C 1 (s) + ˆR(p))/U (1 p)] < βu ( ˆR(p))/U (1) = ˆR(p) η such that the marginal rate of substitution is bounded away from infinity. We therefore obtain the following proposition: Proposition 1 If there is any investment option which generates a safe return on today s investment, the optimal expected marginal rate of substitution between current and future consumption is finite. Proposition 1 implies that Weitzman s dismal theorem does not apply at the optimal investment decision. The difference between our result and Weitzman is an assumption about whether C 1 can meaningfully include adaptation and mitigation. Weitzman claims that C 1 includes all such actions and therefore includes neither investments p nor their returns R(p, s) in his set-up. In general, however, it is doubtful if a safe asset exists as assumed so far. Instead, investments might reasonably be equally at risk from climate change. In the following, we therefore extend the analysis to capture situations in which the returns to investment are uncertain and can even be negative for some states of nature. Here, an interior solution to 1 Note that the other potential corner solution, p = 1, cannot be optimal as U (0) = and U (C 1(s) + ˆR(p)) < U (R(p)) < for ˆR(p) > 0. 4

this investment problem would require U (1 p) + βe[u (C 1 (s) + R(p, s))r (p, s)] = 0 (5) while it would be optimal to invest nothing (p = 0) if β E[U (C 1 (s))r (0, s)] U (1) < 1 (6) If indeed the distribution of C 1 already reflects the optimal choice of all mitigation and adaptation options, a corner solution p = 0 must be optimal. This would be consistent with Weitzman s infinity result, i.e. a situation where βe[u (C 1 (s))/u (1)] = only if for all feasible investment options, condition (6) holds. That is, if βe[u (C 1 (s))r (0, s)]/u (1) < 1. This finding thereby puts a word of caution on using expected marginal willingness to substitute between today s and tomorrow s consumption, i.e. a willingness to pay for investing into a safe asset, as an indicator for CBA. Instead, meaningful cost-benefit analysis must jointly consider marginal willingness to substitute between consumption today and tomorrow and the options/technologies of transfering income. Indeed, (6) implies that even when the marginal willingness to shift consumption into the future is infinity at p = 0, society should not give up all consumption today in order to shift consumption into the future: Proposition 2 A society will never give up all its wealth in order to transfer it into some uncertain future. To demonstrate Proposition 2 formally, we reconsider the left hand side of (5) for p approaching 1. Note that if p > p 0 and R (p, s) > 0, it also follows that R(p, s) > R(p 0, s) > 0. Using this inequality and R (p, s) R, we obtain U (1 p) + βe[u (C 1 (s) + R(p, s))r (p, s)] < U (1 p) + βprob[r (p, s) > 0]E[U (C 1 (s) + R(p, s))r (p, s) R (p, s) > 0)] < U (1 p) + βprob[r (p, s) > 0)]E[U (C 1 (s) + R(p 0, s))r (p 0, s) R (p, s) > 0)] Now note that E[U (C 1 (s) + R(p 0, s))r (p 0, s) R (p, s) > 0)] is bounded from above since 5

C 1 (s) + R(p 0, s) > 0. On the other hand, U (1 p) for p 1. We therefore obtain that the marginal benefit from investing a further unit must be negative for p sufficiently close to 1 which proves Proposition 2. 3 Conclusions A cost-benefit framework for climate change is indeed possible, despite Weitzman s conclusions based on his Dismal Theorem. This conclusion holds even in situations where the expected marginal rate of substitution between consumption today and the future is infinite, at least on the margin. This result puts us back in the realm that we started in: The choice of a climate policy depends on consideration of the discount rate, control costs and effectiveness, and the effects of climate change on future incomes. None of these elements is easy to estimate or uncontroversial to apply. The question still remains of what will happen under future climate scenarios and what can and should be done. Cost-benefit analysis may be deemed the wrong framework with which to make these momentous decisions. But if so, it is not fat-tailed distributions or infinite expected marginal utilities that should motivate this abandonment. 4 References Weitzman, M.L. (2008), On Modeling and Interpreting the Economics of Catastrophic Climate Change, Working Paper. 6