Optimizing S-shaped utility and risk management

Similar documents
Optimizing S-shaped utility and risk management: ineffectiveness of VaR and ES constraints

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers. Carole Bernard (UW), Jit Seng Chen (GGY) and Steven Vanduffel (Vrije Universiteit Brussel)

Portfolio Choice via Quantiles

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Optimal Investment with Deferred Capital Gains Taxes

All Investors are Risk-averse Expected Utility Maximizers

Risk, Coherency and Cooperative Game

Characterization of the Optimum

LECTURE 4: BID AND ASK HEDGING

IEOR E4602: Quantitative Risk Management

Prospect Theory: A New Paradigm for Portfolio Choice

Basic Arbitrage Theory KTH Tomas Björk

Risk Measures for Derivative Securities: From a Yin-Yang Approach to Aerospace Space

3 Arbitrage pricing theory in discrete time.

Multi-period mean variance asset allocation: Is it bad to win the lottery?

Solution Guide to Exercises for Chapter 4 Decision making under uncertainty

A class of coherent risk measures based on one-sided moments

X ln( +1 ) +1 [0 ] Γ( )

Mathematics in Finance

Statistical Methods in Financial Risk Management

Lecture 17. The model is parametrized by the time period, δt, and three fixed constant parameters, v, σ and the riskless rate r.

Risk Minimization Control for Beating the Market Strategies

Mock Examination 2010

Choice under Uncertainty

Chapter 15: Jump Processes and Incomplete Markets. 1 Jumps as One Explanation of Incomplete Markets

Risk Measures and Optimal Risk Transfers

Optimization Models in Financial Mathematics

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 2

A generalized coherent risk measure: The firm s perspective

Optimal Portfolio Liquidation with Dynamic Coherent Risk

MATH3075/3975 FINANCIAL MATHEMATICS TUTORIAL PROBLEMS

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Guarantee valuation in Notional Defined Contribution pension systems

The Black-Scholes Model

Portfolio Optimization using Conditional Sharpe Ratio

Comparative Analyses of Expected Shortfall and Value-at-Risk (2): Expected Utility Maximization and Tail Risk

Problem Set: Contract Theory

arxiv: v2 [q-fin.pr] 23 Nov 2017

Log-Robust Portfolio Management

Dynamic Portfolio Choice II

Problem Set: Contract Theory

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Prudence, risk measures and the Optimized Certainty Equivalent: a note

Why Bankers Should Learn Convex Analysis

Chapter 3 Common Families of Distributions. Definition 3.4.1: A family of pmfs or pdfs is called exponential family if it can be expressed as

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Performance Measurement with Nonnormal. the Generalized Sharpe Ratio and Other "Good-Deal" Measures

Building Consistent Risk Measures into Stochastic Optimization Models

Lecture 8: Asset pricing

Optimal stopping problems for a Brownian motion with a disorder on a finite interval

Value at Risk, Expected Shortfall, and Marginal Risk Contribution, in: Szego, G. (ed.): Risk Measures for the 21st Century, p , Wiley 2004.

A No-Arbitrage Theorem for Uncertain Stock Model

Cost-efficiency and Applications

Illiquidity, Credit risk and Merton s model

Optimal Investment for Generalized Utility Functions

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.pm] 13 Mar 2014

Session 9: The expected utility framework p. 1

Finance: A Quantitative Introduction Chapter 7 - part 2 Option Pricing Foundations

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Department of Mathematics. Mathematics of Financial Derivatives

based on two joint papers with Sara Biagini Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa, Università degli Studi di Perugia

Introduction to Probability Theory and Stochastic Processes for Finance Lecture Notes

Econ 101A Final exam Mo 18 May, 2009.

Finance: Lecture 4 - No Arbitrage Pricing Chapters of DD Chapter 1 of Ross (2005)

The Birth of Financial Bubbles

How do Variance Swaps Shape the Smile?

Portfolio selection with multiple risk measures

Executive Summary: A CVaR Scenario-based Framework For Minimizing Downside Risk In Multi-Asset Class Portfolios

Utility Indifference Pricing and Dynamic Programming Algorithm

Optimal Investment for Worst-Case Crash Scenarios

SYSM 6304: Risk and Decision Analysis Lecture 6: Pricing and Hedging Financial Derivatives

M5MF6. Advanced Methods in Derivatives Pricing

On Risk Measures, Market Making, and Exponential Families

General Equilibrium under Uncertainty

Risk aversion and choice under uncertainty

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Equity correlations implied by index options: estimation and model uncertainty analysis

Distortion operator of uncertainty claim pricing using weibull distortion operator

Economics 101. Lecture 3 - Consumer Demand

induced by the Solvency II project

Strategies for Improving the Efficiency of Monte-Carlo Methods

On Utility Based Pricing of Contingent Claims in Incomplete Markets

Optimal Allocation of Policy Limits and Deductibles

Basics of Asset Pricing. Ali Nejadmalayeri

SOLVENCY AND CAPITAL ALLOCATION

Risk aversion in multi-stage stochastic programming: a modeling and algorithmic perspective

American Option Pricing Formula for Uncertain Financial Market

Lecture Notes 1

Capital requirements, market, credit, and liquidity risk

u (x) < 0. and if you believe in diminishing return of the wealth, then you would require

CONSISTENCY AMONG TRADING DESKS

RISK MINIMIZING PORTFOLIO OPTIMIZATION AND HEDGING WITH CONDITIONAL VALUE-AT-RISK

Managing Value at Risk Using Put Options

Financial Giffen Goods: Examples and Counterexamples

Option Pricing Formula for Fuzzy Financial Market

Forecast Horizons for Production Planning with Stochastic Demand

Pricing theory of financial derivatives

Risk Measurement in Credit Portfolio Models

The Uncertain Volatility Model

On the Lower Arbitrage Bound of American Contingent Claims

Transcription:

Optimizing S-shaped utility and risk management Ineffectiveness of VaR and ES constraints John Armstrong (KCL), Damiano Brigo (Imperial) Quant Summit March 2018

Are ES constraints effective against rogue traders? We will approach this question as follows Develop a mathematical model for how a rogue trader will behave. Use this to determine their behaviour in some standard market models, in particular the Black-Scholes model, when risk constraints are applied. Consider VaR, ES and constraints based on expected utility. Calculate the consequences of their behaviour and decide if it is desirable. Complimentary to the axiomatic approach e.g.: von Neummann and Morgenstern gave an axiomatic approach to preferences over probability distributions that leads to utility functions. Artzner, Delbaen, Eber and Heath gave an axiomatic approach to coherent risk measures that suggests VaR is not a good risk measure, but ES (aka CVaR) is. etc. etc. There is a large literature.

Utility functions Theorem (von Neumann Morgernstern) Let be a preference relation defined on probability densities satisfying 3 relatively uncontroversial axioms plus the independence axiom L M = pl + (1 p)n pm + (1 p)n then can be given in terms of a utility function u : R R by L M iff E(u(L)) E(u(M)). One might additionally expect u will be increasing (preference for profit); u will be concave (risk-aversion). Utility Terminal Wealth

S-shaped utility functions Kahneman and Tversky found in psychological experiments that most people appear to have S-shaped utility curves, so they are not always risk averse. Utility Terminal Wealth A rogue trader loses their job and reputation but nothing more if they experience large losses. A limited liability company will have S-shaped utility. We will model rogue traders as optimizing an S-shaped utility function.

Risk constraints We will consider risk-constraints of the form ρ(x ) L where ρ is a risk figure depending on the distribution of the portfolio payoff X and L is a risk limit. ρ could be: a Value at Risk (VaR) figure, an Expected Shortfall (ES also known as CVaR) figure an expected disutility E(u R (X )). u R is the risk-manager s utility not the trader s utility. Definitions The 5%-Value at Risk (VaR) of a portfolio over a given time horizon corresponds to maximum loss experienced in the 95% best-case scenarios. The 5%-Expected Shortfall (ES) over the same time horizon corresponds to the expected loss in the 5% worst-case scenarios. More precisely if α [0, 1] ES α (X ) = 1 α α 0 VaR α (X )dα.

Formal defintion For this talk, an function u : R R is S-shaped if: It is increasing. u(x) 0 for x 0. u(x) 0 for x 0. For sufficiently small x, u(x) C( x) η for some constant C > 0 and η (0, 1). We say it is risk-seeking on the left. For sufficiently large x, u(x) Cx η for some constant C > 0 and η (0, 1). We say it is risk-averse on the right.

Modelling the Market We assume both trader and risk manager agree on the probability model P underlying the dynamics of the market. We assume that prices in the model are given by discounted expectations in a risk-neutral probability model Q. We consider only the case of a constant risk-free rate r. We assume that the market is complete. That is we assume that arbitrary derivative securities can be purchased at the risk-neutral price (so long as this price exists). Examples The Black Scholes Merton market in continuous time where one can trade in the stock and a risk free bond. A discrete time version of the Black Scholes Merton market where any derivative can be purchased at the Black Scholes price so long as it has a fixed maturity T and European style exercise.

The optimization problem Find a sequence of investments X 1, X 2,... achieving optimal trader utility lim i E(u T (X i )) = sup X E(u T (X )) subject to a cost constraint E Q (X ) e rt C = C and a risk-management constraint ρ(x ) L. Remark We seek a sequence of investments because we cannot always expect the supremum to be achieved. For example it is obvious that in markets with no risk-constraints there will normally be no limit on the expected utility other than sup(u T ) itself.

Results Subject to some additional requirements on the market which are all satisfied in the Black Scholes cases we find: For ES constraints, the only limit on the expected utility that can be achieved is sup(u T ). Hence for VaR constraints, the only limit on the expected utility that can be achieved is also sup(u T ). Expected disutility constraints E(u R (X )) L written in terms of a risk-manager s concave increasing utility function u R typically DO limit the utility that can be achieved. (This result requires some further assumptions on the risk-managers utility function). The main step to proving these results is reducing the optimization problem to a 1-dimensional problem that is easy to solve.

Interpretation Our interpretation is that Rogue traders will not be concerned if they are obliged to act under ES and VaR constraints. The utility they can achieve is unaffected. Moreover, for reasonable risk manager utility functions u R, rogue traders will choose strategies that have unboundedly negative risk manager utilities. In brief: ES and VaR constraints don t work. Expected utility constraints do work.

Reduction to one dimension: the financial intuition Recall the problem we wish to solve is Maximize E(u T (X )) subject to a cost constraint E Q (X ) C and a risk-management constraint ρ(x ) L. Remark Note that all that matters are the P and Q measure distributions of X. Intuitively the trader can decide how much money to put on a specific event ω by just looking at the ratio of the P and Q measure probabilities.

Rigorous formulation Theorem (Subject to a very mild technical condition) We may restrict attention to X of the form X = f ( dq dp ) = f where f is an increasing function and is the Radon-Nikodym derivative. ( 1 F dq dp dq dp ( )) dq dp In other words, go long on events you think are under-priced and go short on events you think are over-priced. Buy low, sell high. The proof relies on the Hardy Littlewood theory of rearrangements. A general version of this result has been found independently by Xunyu Zhou.

Rewriting the optimization problem Subject to very mild technical conditions, we may write our ES optimization problem as follows. Find a payoff function f : [0, 1] R depending only on 1 F dq dp maximizing subject to a cost constraint 1 0 u T (x)dx and an ES constraint 1 0 f (x)q(x)dx C 1 p f (x)dx L p 0 where q is the probability density function of X = 1 F dq dp ( dq dp ). X is uniformly distributed.

Pictorial representation We must choose an increasing payoff function f to maximize 1 0 u T (f (x))dx subject to p 0 f (x)dx L and 1 0 f (x)q(x)dx C. q(x) payoff f (X) 4 2 Out[79]= 0 U 1 - F dq 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 dp dq dp -2-4 The density q(x) shown is for the Black Scholes model. If q(x) as x 0 then arbitrary expected trader utilities u T can be achieved using step functions as shown.

Main negative result If sup q(x) = then VaR and ES constraints are ineffective in constraining a trader with S-shaped utility. Digital payoffs of the form shown below can be used to achieve arbitrarily high trader utilities subject to the cost and risk constraints. The only limit is sup u T itself. q(x) payoff f (X) 4 2 Out[79]= 0 U 1 - F dq 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 dp dq dp -2-4

The Black Scholes case In the P measure In the Q measure z T := log S T N(log S 0 + (µ 1 2 σ2 )T, σ T ) z T := log S T N(log S 0 + (r 1 2 σ2 )T, σ T ) Write p(z T ) for the pdf of z T in the P measure. q(z T ) for the Q measure pdf. ( ) exp dq dp (z T ) = q(z T ) p(z T ) = exp (z T log S 0 (r 1 2 σ2 )T ) 2 2σ 2 T ( (z T log S 0 (µ 1 2 σ2 )T ) 2 2σ 2 T (µ r)(t(µ+r σ 2 )+2 log(s 0 ) 2z T) = e 2σ 2 as z T if µ > r )

The requirement (1) is automatically satisfied in the Black Scholes model. Main positive result Suppose the risk-manager s utility function is given by { ( x) γ x 0 u R (x) = 0 otherwise for γ in (1, ). Suppose they impose a limit E P (u(x )) L. Suppose the trader has S-shaped utility and moreover is difficult to satisfy which means that if we prohibit short selling, they cannot achieve the supremum of their utility function. Suppose that is finite. ( dq E P dp γ R γ R 1 Then the risk manager s expected utility constraint is binding. ) (1)

Utility Terminal Wealth Proof of result We restrict attention to traders with limited-liability. For any increasing f we can find p such that { f (X ) 0 x > p f (X ) = f (X ) 0 x < p For fixed choice of p the problem is then the convex problem minimize subject to and 1 p u T (f (x))dx 0 u R(f (x))dx L q(x)f (x)dx C p 1 0

Example solutions in Black-Scholes model Note payoff profiles drawn against S T rather than uniform X. Payoff 100 Out[602]= -100 0.7 0.8 0.9 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.3 ST ur -1 ur -10 ur -100 95%-ES Arbitrage -200

Incomplete markets The most obvious criticism of our result is that we assume a complete market. Definition An α-es arbitrage portfolio is a portfolio which has: a negative expected shortfall at confidence level α a non-positive cost Justification: Since the expected shortfall is negative, the payoff must sometimes be positive. If such a portfolio exists, then a trader can buy arbitrarily large quantities without violating ES or cost constraints. If the trader has limited liability then their expected utility will only increase as they buy larger quantities of the portfolio. If an α-es arbitrage portfolio exists, α-es limits will be ineffective.

Summary In general VaR and ES limits are not effective in curbing the risks taken by rogue traders. Limits set using concave increasing utility functions can be effective in reasonable market models.