Rational Choice and Moral Monotonicity. James C. Cox

Similar documents
Moral Costs and Rational Choice: Theory and Experimental Evidence

Provision versus Appropriation in Symmetric and Asymmetric Social Dilemmas. James C. Cox, Elinor Ostrom, Vjollca Sadiraj, and James M.

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES

Topic 3 Social preferences

Taking, Giving, and Impure Altruism in Dictator Games

Social preferences I and II

Outline for today. Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games. General-sum games. General-sum games. Dominated pure strategies

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

PhD Qualifier Examination

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

FIGURE A1.1. Differences for First Mover Cutoffs (Round one to two) as a Function of Beliefs on Others Cutoffs. Second Mover Round 1 Cutoff.

On the Performance of the Lottery Procedure for Controlling Risk Preferences *

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 2

Internet Appendix to: Common Ownership, Competition, and Top Management Incentives

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Suggested solutions to the 6 th seminar, ECON4260

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Macroeconomics and finance

While the story has been different in each case, fundamentally, we ve maintained:

Lecture 11: Critiques of Expected Utility

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

NASH PROGRAM Abstract: Nash program

CHOICE THEORY, UTILITY FUNCTIONS AND RISK AVERSION

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

EC202. Microeconomic Principles II. Summer 2009 examination. 2008/2009 syllabus

(a) Describe the game in plain english and find its equivalent strategic form.

INDIVIDUAL AND HOUSEHOLD WILLINGNESS TO PAY FOR PUBLIC GOODS JOHN QUIGGIN

Rational theories of finance tell us how people should behave and often do not reflect reality.

Bargaining and Coalition Formation

A Geometric Measure for the Violation of Utility Maximization

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Bargaining Theory and Solutions

The Core of a Strategic Game *

Lecture 5. Varian, Ch. 8; MWG, Chs. 3.E, 3.G, and 3.H. 1 Summary of Lectures 1, 2, and 3: Production theory and duality

Axiomatic Reference Dependence in Behavior Toward Others and Toward Risk

Subgame Perfect Cooperation in an Extensive Game

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions.

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Other Regarding Preferences

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia.

A. Introduction to choice under uncertainty 2. B. Risk aversion 11. C. Favorable gambles 15. D. Measures of risk aversion 20. E.

Appendix A. Additional estimation results for section 5.

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 5 Games and Strategy (Ch. 4)

SF2972 GAME THEORY Infinite games

Lecture 1 Introduction and Definition of TU games

Do Government Subsidies Increase the Private Supply of Public Goods?

Psychology and Economics Field Exam August 2012

THEORIES OF BEHAVIOR IN PRINCIPAL-AGENT RELATIONSHIPS WITH HIDDEN ACTION*

Aggressive Corporate Tax Behavior versus Decreasing Probability of Fiscal Control (Preliminary and incomplete)

* Financial support was provided by the National Science Foundation (grant number

Tit for tat: Foundations of preferences for reciprocity in strategic settings

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Econ 618: Topic 11 Introduction to Coalitional Games

Mock Examination 2010

Counting Basics. Venn diagrams

Correcting for Survival Effects in Cross Section Wage Equations Using NBA Data

MS&E 246: Lecture 5 Efficiency and fairness. Ramesh Johari

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

USING LOTTERIES TO FINANCE PUBLIC GOODS: THEORY AND EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE

Yao s Minimax Principle

THE PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIVERSITY. Department of Economics. January Written Portion of the Comprehensive Examination for

Lecture 6 Introduction to Utility Theory under Certainty and Uncertainty

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Random Variables and Applications OPRE 6301

Market Liquidity and Performance Monitoring The main idea The sequence of events: Technology and information

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES

A Core Concept for Partition Function Games *

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

EXTENSIVE AND NORMAL FORM GAMES

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

Bias in Reduced-Form Estimates of Pass-through

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

Tema 2. Edgeworth s Exchange Theory

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours

Choice under risk and uncertainty

Lecture 1 Definitions from finance

Game Theory with Applications to Finance and Marketing, I

ECON Micro Foundations

Equivalence Nucleolus for Partition Function Games

Self-Serving Bias and Ultimatum Bargaining

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

Practice Questions for Mid-Term Examination - I. In answering questions just consider symmetric and stationary allocations!

MAT 4250: Lecture 1 Eric Chung

Uncertainty in Equilibrium

Homework #2 Psychology 101 Spr 03 Prof Colin Camerer

Transcription:

Rational Choice and Moral Monotonicity James C. Cox

Acknowledgement of Coauthors Today s lecture uses content from: J.C. Cox and V. Sadiraj (2010). A Theory of Dictators Revealed Preferences J.C. Cox, J.A. List, M. Price, V. Sadiraj & A. Samek (2017). Moral Costs and Rational Choice: Theory and Experimental Evidence J.C. Cox, V. Sadiraj & S. Tang (2018). Rational Choice in Games with Externalities and Contractions

Two Well-Known Anomalies Andreoni (1995): subjects are more cooperative in a public good game than in a common pool game with the same feasible set of payoffs Bardsley (2008) and List (2007): adding take opportunities to a give-only dictator game changes behavior First Question: what are the implications of these anomalies for: Preference theory? Rational choice theory?

Preference Theory and Rational Choice Theory Convex Preference Theory o Indifference curves o Axioms of a preference ordering o Utility function o Generalized Axiom of Revealed Preference (GARP) Rational Choice Theory o Choice function o Contraction Consistency Axiom (CCA), a.k.a. Property Sen (1971)

Foundations for the Discussion GARP utility function that represents revealed preferences CCA complete and transitive ordering of choices (for singleton choice sets) Convex preference theory is a special case of rational choice theory.

Definitions GARP: if then p i p p x, i x i j k p k x k i p j p x j x j r,, x, for all i, j, r,,s, k. p s p x s x s k If x i is revealed preferred to x k then x k is not strictly directly revealed to x i. CCA: For any feasible sets F and G and choice sets C(F) and C(G): [ x C( F) and x G F] x C( G) An allocation, x that is chosen from F is also chosen from any subset G of F that contains x. (a.k.a. independence of irrelevant alternatives )

Basic Distinction Abstract theory of preferences or choice for commodities Interpretation of commodity Example: indifference curves for commodity X and commodity Y What are the commodities? o my hamburgers and my hotdogs OR o my hamburgers and your hamburgers

Data from Andreoni (1995) and Many Subsequent Authors Choices in a public good game and a common pool game with the same feasible set are significantly different: o Subjects allocate more to the public account (less to their private accounts) in the public good game * This robust finding is inconsistent with CCA because any set is a subset of itself; hence, from CCA: [ x C( F) and x G F] x C( G) [ x C( G) and x F G] x C( F)

Bardsley (2008), List (2007), Cappelen, et al. (2013) Dictators change their allocations when presented a chance to take as well as to give to others. In the typical dictator game: o The experiment is framed such that giving nothing is the least generous act, and o Substantial sums of money are given away (Engel, 2011). But if subjects are allowed to take as well as give money then they give much less to the other player on average. * So What?

Percentage Data from List (2007) List (2007) 50% 45% 40% 35% 30% 25% 20% Baseline Take $1 15% 10% 5% 0% 1 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.5 3 3.5 4 4.5 5 Amount Transferred

Theoretical Interpretation of List (2007) Data In order for the data to be consistent with convex preference theory: o The height of the blue bar at 0 must equal the sum of the heights of the red bars at -1 and 0 o The heights of the blue and red bars must be the same at all other transfer numbers In order for the data to be consistent with rational choice theory: o No red bar to the right of -1 can be taller than the corresponding blue bar

List (2007), Bardsley (2008), Cappelen, et al. (2013) Data from these experiments are: o Inconsistent with convex preference theory (including social preferences models) o Consistent (almost completely) with rational choice theory These experiments: o Stress-test convex preference theory o Endowments and action sets are not well suited to stress-test rational choice theory

Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient Our Dictator Experiment Feasible Sets: [B, C] for Give or Take, [A, C] for Symmetric 30 Inequality (I) 30 Equal (Q) 30 A E Envy (E) 25 25 A Q 25 20 A I 20 B Q 20 B E 15 B I 15 15 C E 10 10 C Q 10 5 C I 5 5 0 0 5 Allocation 10 15 to Dictator 20 25 30 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator 0 0 5 Allocation 10 15 to Dictator 20 25 30 This figure portrays the feasible allocations for each treatment and action set. Participants in the Give or Take action sets can choose from [B, C] Participants in the Symmetric action set can choose from [A, C]. Actual feasible choices are ordered pairs of integers on the line segments.

Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient 30 Inequality (I) Inequality (I) 25 20 15 10 30 A I B I 5 C I 25 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator 20 A I 15 10 B I 5 C I 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator

Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient 30 Equal (Q) Equal (Q) 25 A Q 20 15 30 B Q 10 C Q 5 25 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator 20 A Q 15 B Q 10 C Q 5 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator

Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient 30 A E Envy (E) Envy (E) 25 20 B E 15 30 10 C E A E 5 0 25 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator 20 B E 15 10 C E 5 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator

Some Results from Our Give, Take, and Symmetric Dictator Treatments for Extant Theory Data are inconsistent with rational choice theory (CCA) Hence, data are inconsistent with convex preference theory, including several social preferences models: o Inequality aversion (Fehr & Schmidt1999; Bolton & Ockenfells 2000) o Quasi-maxmin (Charness & Rabin 2002) o Egocentric altruism (Cox & Sadiraj 2007) Data are inconsistent with: Reference Dependent Model (Koszegi and Rabin 2006)

The High Priest Questions the Faith For decades A.K. Sen was central to development of rational choice theory. But in a 1993 Econometrica article he wrote: Internal consistency of choice has been a central concept in demand theory, social choice theory, decision theory, behavioral economics, and related fields. It is argued here that this idea is essentially confused, and there is no way of determining whether a choice function is consistent or not without referring to something external to choice behavior (such as objectives, values, or norms).

But Don t Throw Out the Baby with the Bath Water Our challenge is how to extend the theory, as called for by Sen, while preserving the central feature that makes it empirically testable: objective restrictions on observable choices. We respond by defining moral reference points that are observable features of feasible sets. Moral Monotonicity Axiom (MMA) is an extension of CCA that incorporates these observable moral reference points.

We Incorporate Two Intuitions into Rational Ch. Th. My moral constraints on interacting with you depend on o The minimum payoff each of us can receive in the game o My property rights in the game

Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient Equal (Q) Envy (E) 30 30 A E 25 A Q 25 B E 20 B Q 20 15 15 C E 10 C Q 10 5 5 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator

An Illustrative Example of Moral Reference Points Consider the N = 2 case of dictator games in the give vs. take literature: o Let (m,y) denote an ordered pair of money payoffs for the dictator m = my payoff and the recipient y = your payoff o Let F denote the dictator s compact feasible set o Let m o and y o denote maximum feasible payoffs: o o m ( F) max{ m ( m, y) F} and y ( F) max{ y ( m, y) F}

Illustrative Example (cont.) We assume an agent s moral reference point is a function of the minimal expectations point, M, defined by: o m ( F) max{ m ( m, y ( F)) F} and y ( F) max{ y ( m ( F), y) F} o * *

Illustrative Example (cont.) Moral reference point also depends on payoff entitlement from the decision maker s endowment. We propose as a moral reference point an ordered pair that o Agrees with the minimal expectations point on the second (recipient s) payoff dimension and o Is a convex combination of the minimal expectations point and the initial endowment e m on the first (dictator s) payoff dimension. o For dictator game feasible sets, the moral reference points are given by: r f (( m ( F) e ), y ( F)) 1 1 2 2 m

Moral Reference Points in Treatment Q 23 A Q 15 B Q Take Endowment = Symmetric Endowment 7 r S r T r G C Q Give Endowment 0 7 11 15 19 23

Let x o ij Moral Reference Point for n 2 be the maximum payoff player i gets when player j gets her maximum, for all j i Define i ( S) * min j i The minimal expectations point is the vector x (1 * (S),2 * (S),...,n * (S)) Player 1 s, moral reference point is s 1 r = ( 1 2 (1 * (S) + e 1 ),2 * (S),...,n * (S)) o ij when her endowment is e 1

Let Moral Monotonicity Axiom (MMA) denote weakly larger or weakly smaller. One has: r r r r MMA : If G F, g f and g f then x C( F) G i i i i y x, y C( G) i i In words: Suppose that G is a subset of F that contains some choice x from F. Suppose also that the moral reference points of F and G differ from each other only with respect to the value of dimension i. Then if the moral reference point in G is weakly more favorable to individual i then no choice from G allocates him less than x. Similarly, if the moral reference point in G is weakly less favorable to individual i then no choice from G allocates him more than x.

MMA Compared to CCA * Note that if F and G have the same moral reference point then MMA is equivalent to CCA.

Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient Allocation to Recepient Our Dictator Experiment Feasible Sets: [B, C] for Give or Take, [A, C] for Symmetric 30 Inequality (I) 30 Equal (Q) 30 A E Envy (E) 25 25 A Q 25 20 A I 20 B Q 20 B E 15 B I 15 15 C E 10 10 C Q 10 5 C I 5 5 0 0 5 Allocation 10 15 to Dictator 20 25 30 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Allocation to Dictator 0 0 5 Allocation 10 15 to Dictator 20 25 30 This figure portrays the feasible allocations for each treatment and action set. Participants in the Give or Take action sets can choose from [B, C] Participants in the Symmetric action set can choose from [A, C]. Actual feasible choices are ordered pairs of integers on the line segments.

25 Moral Reference Points for Treatments 20 r 2 (recepient) 15 10 ES ET EG QS QT QG 5 IS IT IG 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 r 1 (dictator)

Predictions for r2 Effects on Recipient s Payoff Predicted effect of r2 on dictator s choice of recipient s payoff: o Contraction Consistency Axiom: no effect o Moral Monotonicity Axiom: positive effect

Tests for r2 Effects on Recipient s Payoff Recipient s Final Payoff r 1 = 15 r 1 = 19 r 1 = 11 r 2 [+] 0.674*** 0.668*** 0.415* 0.391* 0.330** 0.328** (0.187) (0.186) (0.215) (0.221) (0.155) (0.151) Constant 6.145*** 6.955*** 6.435*** 5.616*** 8.620*** 9.341*** (1.548) (2.417) (1.143) (1.895) (1.480) (1.797) no yes no yes no yes Observations 207 207 147 147 131 131-261.3-258.3-224.8-221.4-225.9-219.4 Demographics Loglikelihood Notes: Entries are Tobit estimated coefficients. MMA predicted sign in square brackets. Demographics include gender, race, GPA, religion, major and study year. Standard errors in parentheses. *** p<0.001, **p<0.05, p*<0.1

Predictions for r1 and r2 Effects on Transfers Marginal Effect of r1 o Contraction Consistency Axiom: No effect o Moral Monotonicity Axiom: Negative Effect Marginal Effect of r2 o Contraction Consistency Axiom: Effect equals -1 o Moral Monotonicity Axiom: Effect is between -1 and 0

Tests for r1 and r2 Effects on Transfers Dep. Variable Hurdle Model Tobit Model Transfer (1) (2) (1) (2) r 1-0.058** -0.055** -0.098** -0.104** (0.027) (0.027) (0.047) (0.047) r 2-0.319*** -0.314*** -0.497*** -0.487*** (0.047) (0.047) (0.091) (0.090) Demographics no yes no yes Observations 612 612 612 612

Summary Results from Our Give, Take, and Symmetric Dictator Treatments CCA is rejected in favor of MMA.

Application to Experiment in Korenok et al. (2014) Endowments are at points 1, 3, 6, 8 and 9 CCA implies choice is invariant to the endowment MMA implies allocation to the recipient varies inversely with dictator s endowment because r r r 1 2 9

Application to Experiment in Korenok et al. (cont.) Data from their experiment is Inconsistent with o CCA, hence GARP and social preferences models o Warm glow model in Korenok et al. (2013) Consistent with MMA

EXPERIMENT Cox, Sadiraj, and Tang (2018) Payoff equivalent public good (PG), common pool (CP), and mixed games (MG) o Within-subjects and between-subjects design o Endogenous contractions of feasible sets THEORETICAL RESULTS CCA implies play is invariant o Across PG, CP, and MG o To non-binding contractions of feasible sets MMA implies contributions to the public account are o Ordered as PG > MG > CP o Increasing in the lower bound, b of non-binding contractions of feasible sets

Choices in the Experiment Use t-test for allocations and Pearson chi2 test for free riding. Choices of subjects in our experiment are characterized by: (i) Larger public account (g) allocations (one-sided p-value=0.063) and less free-riding (one-sided p-value=0.002) in provision than appropriation game data (ii) Larger public account (g) allocations (one-sided p-value=0.08) but similar free-riding (one-sided p-value=0.124) in provision than mixed game data (iii) Similar public account (g) allocations (one-sided p-values=0.424) but less free-riding (one-sided p-value=0.038) in mixed than appropriation game data.

Best Response g Allocations (no contraction, tobit, random effects) Dep.Variable: g allocation (1) (2) (3) (4) Guessed Other s allocation 1.005*** 1.014*** 1.022*** 1.024*** (0.079) (0.079) (0.079) (0.079) g o (Initial allocation) -0.131** -0.141** -0.132** -0.146** (0.065) (0.066) (0.065) (0.065) Demographics no yes yes yes Self Image no no yes yes Image of Others no no no yes Constant -0.662-0.989-1.203-0.831 (0.550) (0.763) (0.787) (0.798) Observations 554 554 554 554 Log. Likelihood -1019-1018 -1014-1012

Best Response g Allocations (with contractions, tobit, random effects) Dep.Var: g Allocation Provision Game Appropriation Game (1) (2) (1) (2) Guessed Other s allocation 0.694*** 0.711*** 0.661*** 0.656*** (0.093) (0.093) (0.130) (0.128) Contraction (lower bound) 0.769*** 0.784*** 0.767*** 0.774*** (0.168) (0.161) (0.232) (0.226) Demographics no yes no yes Constant -0.626-1.309* -2.371*** -3.927*** (0.571) (0.765) (0.903) (1.502) Observations 240 240 240 240 Nr of Subjects 80 80 (left-, un-,right-) censored (70,129,41) (87, 123,30) Standard errors in parentheses; *** p<0.01, ** p<0.05, * p<0.1

Data are Generally Inconsistent with CCA but Consistent with MMA Result 1. Public good game elicits higher avg. allocation to the public account; common pool game elicits more free-riding (allocations of 0 or 1). Result 2. Allocation to the public account decreases with the initial endowment of the public account. Result 3. Non-binding lower bounds on public account allocations induce higher average allocations to the public account, conditional on other s allocation.

Some Additional Applications of MMA to Data in the Literature MMA is consistent with Andreoni & Miller (2002) data MMA is consistent with both dictator data and elicited norms in the bully game (Krupka and Weber 2013) MMA is consistent with data from sharing and sorting experiment (Lazear et al. 2012) MMA is consistent with data from strategic games with contractions: Moonlighting (Abbink et al.) and investment games (Berg, et al. 1995) Carrot, stick, and carrot/stick games (Andreoni et al. 2003)

Conclusion MMA provides an extension of rational choice theory that rationalizes otherwise anomalous data from many experiments

Sen s Two Properties for Non-singleton Choice Sets Property :if G F then F G G * * Property :if G F and G F then G F * * * *

Let f belong to both Proof of Proposition 1 * F and G. Consider any g from g f have the same moral reference point,, g f and g f, i i i i i G *. As G and F r r MMA requires that. These inequalities can be simultaneously satisfied if and only if, g = f i.e. f belongs to Property M. Note, though, that any choice g in * G which concludes the proof for * G must coincide with f, an implication of which is G must be a singleton. So, if the intersection * of * F and G is not empty then choices satisfy property M.

Implications for Andreoni and Miller (2002) Experiment

MMA Implies Tighter Restrictions than WARP for the Andreoni and Miller (2002) Experiment

Rationalizing Data from the Bully Game (Krupka and Weber 2013) MMA predicts dictator game choices & social norms elicited by Krupka and Weber Moral reference points o (5, 0) in the standard dictator game o (2.5, 0) in the bully dictator game Hence, MMA requires choices in the bully treatment to be drawn from a distribution that is less favorable to the dictator than the distribution of choices in the standard game Implies higher amount for the recipient and positive estimate for the bully treatment Mean amounts & results of ordered logistic regression support the predictions of MMA Reported distribution of elicited norms is also consistent with MMA

Rationalizing Data from Sharing and Sorting Exp. (Lazear et al. 2012) EXPERIMENT 2 Random selection of one of several decisions for payoff Decision 1: subjects play a distribute $10 dictator game Decision 2: subjects can o Sort out of $10 dictator game, and be paid $10 (other gets $0), or o Sort in and play the distribute $10 dictator game Other decision tasks: o Subjects can sort out of $S dictator game, and be paid $10 (other gets $0), or o Sort in and play the distribute $S dictator game o S varied from 10.50 to 20

Rationalizing Data from Sharing and Sorting Exp. (cont.) Explaining sorting into a S > 10 game and keeping more than 10 is straightforward Many sorted out, and got 10, when they could have sorted in & retained more than 10 MMA model is consistent with the data: o Subject has right to choose the ordered pair of payoffs (10,0) by sorting out o This provides a (10,0) endowment for the two-step game o Sj is the amount that can be allocated in treatment j o Dictator s sharing options include 0 and Sj, hence the minimal expectations point for the two-stage game is (0,0) o The moral reference point is 1 ( r1, r2) ( 2 10,0) (5,0) if the player sorts in ( r1, r2) (0,0) if the player sorts out

Rationalizing Data from Sharing and Sorting Exp. (cont.) o Let preferences consistent with MMA be represented by a utility function o Examples show that u (10,0), from sorting out, can be larger than u( S y 5, y) for S y 10,from sorting in