Nash Bargaining Part I - The Continuous Case

Similar documents
Economics 2202 (Section 05) Macroeconomic Theory Practice Problem Set 3 Suggested Solutions Professor Sanjay Chugh Fall 2014

Economics 325 Intermediate Macroeconomic Analysis Practice Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions Professor Sanjay Chugh Spring 2011

Problem Set 8 Topic BI: Externalities. a) What is the profit-maximizing level of output?

Importantly, note that prices are not functions of the expenditure on advertising that firm 1 makes during the first period.

Economics 602 Macroeconomic Theory and Policy Problem Set 4 Suggested Solutions Professor Sanjay Chugh Summer 2010

Dynamic Pricing of Di erentiated Products

Sequential Procurement Auctions and Their Effect on Investment Decisions

Output and Expenditure

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 9

TOTAL PART 1 / 50 TOTAL PART 2 / 50

0NDERZOEKSRAPPORT NR TAXES, DEBT AND FINANCIAL INTERMEDIARIES C. VAN HULLE. Wettelijk Depot : D/1986/2376/4

Intermediating Auctioneers

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Bidding for network size

Kyle Bagwell and Robert W. Staiger. Revised: November 1993

Valuation of Bermudan-DB-Underpin Option

Asymmetric Integration *

Optimal Disclosure Decisions When There are Penalties for Nondisclosure

ARTICLE IN PRESS. Journal of Health Economics xxx (2011) xxx xxx. Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect. Journal of Health Economics

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

FOREST CITY INDUSTRIAL PARK FIN AN CIAL RETURNS EXECUTIVE SUMMARY

Ranking dynamics and volatility. Ronald Rousseau KU Leuven & Antwerp University, Belgium

Strategic Dynamic Sourcing from Competing Suppliers: The Value of Commitment

CONSUMPTION-LABOR FRAMEWORK SEPTEMBER 19, (aka CONSUMPTION-LEISURE FRAMEWORK) THE THREE MACRO (AGGREGATE) MARKETS. The Three Macro Markets

Title: Bertrand-Edgeworth Competition, Demand Uncertainty, and Asymmetric Outcomes * Authors: Stanley S. Reynolds Bart J. Wilson

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 3

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

Exogenous Information, Endogenous Information and Optimal Monetary Policy

CONSUMPTION-LEISURE FRAMEWORK SEPTEMBER 20, 2010 THE THREE MACRO (AGGREGATE) MARKETS. The Three Macro Markets. Goods Markets.

Game Theory Fall 2003

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

The Impact of Capacity Costs on Bidding Strategies in Procurement Auctions

Globalization, Jobs, and Welfare: The Roles of Social Protection and Redistribution 1

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

The Simple Economics of White Elephants

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

Experimentation, Private Observability of Success, and the Timing of Monitoring

At a cost-minimizing input mix, the MRTS (ratio of marginal products) must equal the ratio of factor prices, or. f r

Risk Sharing and Adverse Selection with Asymmetric Information on Risk Preference

Class Notes: Week 6. Multinomial Outcomes

Licensing and Patent Protection

AUDITING COST OVERRUN CLAIMS *

Finitely repeated simultaneous move game.

Prices, Social Accounts and Economic Models

Repeated Games. September 3, Definitions: Discounting, Individual Rationality. Finitely Repeated Games. Infinitely Repeated Games

Clipping Coupons: Redemption of Offers with Forward-Looking Consumers

Notes for Section: Week 4

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 5: Repeated Games

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati.

Decision, Risk & Operations Working Papers Series

IS-LM model. Giovanni Di Bartolomeo Macro refresh course Economics PhD 2012/13

Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica

Associate Professor Jiancai PI, PhD Department of Economics School of Business, Nanjing University

Should platforms be allowed to charge ad valorem fees?

Availability Analysis with Opportunistic Maintenance of a Two Component Deteriorating System

FDPE Microeconomics 3 Spring 2017 Pauli Murto TA: Tsz-Ning Wong (These solution hints are based on Julia Salmi s solution hints for Spring 2015.

MIDTERM ANSWER KEY GAME THEORY, ECON 395

First-price equilibrium and revenue equivalence in a sequential procurement auction model

Finite Memory and Imperfect Monitoring

A solution by stochastic iteration method for nonlinear Black- Scholes equation with transaction cost and volatile portfolio risk in Hilbert space

CHAPTER 14: REPEATED PRISONER S DILEMMA

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

On the Welfare Benefits of an International Currency

Explanatory Memorandum

ON TRANSACTION COSTS IN STOCK TRADING

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Repeated Games

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2017

Say you have $X today and can earn an annual interest rate r by investing it. Let FV denote the future value of your investment and t = time.

Properties of the nonsymmetric Robinson-Schensted-Knuth algorithm

Study on Rural Microfinance System s Defects and Risk Control Based on Operational Mode

Page 80. where C) refers to estimation cell (defined by industry and, for selected industries, region)

Voluntary Prices vs. Voluntary Quantities

Repeated Games. EC202 Lectures IX & X. Francesco Nava. January London School of Economics. Nava (LSE) EC202 Lectures IX & X Jan / 16

Are Hard Budget Constraints for Sub-National GovernmentsAlwaysEfficient?

Decision-making Method for Low-rent Housing Construction Investment. Wei Zhang*, Liwen You

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Imagine barriers between you and other buyers or sellers: legal, spatial, social, or temporal

Game Theory Fall 2006

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

Problem Set 3: Suggested Solutions

13.1 Infinitely Repeated Cournot Oligopoly

Lecture 7: The Theory of Demand. Where does demand come from? What factors influence choice? A simple model of choice

Optimal selling rules for repeated transactions.

CHAPTER 9 BUDGETARY PLANNING SUMMARY OF QUESTIONS BY STUDY OBJECTIVES AND BLOOM S TAXONOMY. True-False Statements. Multiple Choice Questions

Outline for Dynamic Games of Complete Information

Bargaining Order and Delays in Multilateral Bargaining with Asymmetric Sellers

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Repeated games OR 8 and 9, and FT 5

The Simple Economics of White Elephants

Exogenous Information, Endogenous Information and Optimal Monetary Policy

Technische Universität Ilmenau Institut für Mathematik

Repeated Games. Econ 400. University of Notre Dame. Econ 400 (ND) Repeated Games 1 / 48

Efficient Pricing of European Options with Stochastic Interest Rate Using Fourier Transform Method

Multi-Firm Mergers with Leaders and Followers

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: August 7, 2017

Optimal Information Design for Reputation Building

Transcription:

Nash Bargaining Part I - The Continuous Case Prajit K. Dutta Satoru Takahashi January 15, 2013 Abstrat This paper onsiders finite horizon alternating move two player bargaining with a ontinuum of agreements. Two models are studied. The first is a variant of the Rubinstein model in whih an agreement, one reahed, is never broken. The seond model is new to the literature and allows for repeated bargains. In this model, an agreement an last for a few periods, be followed by periods of disagreement and then, potentially, a new and different agreement an emerge. It is shown that, if the Pareto frontier is onave, then in both models the unique limiting equilbrium is the Nash Solution, the agreement that maximizes the produt of player payoffs. 1 Introdution This paper onsiders finite horizon two player bargaining, an environment in whih the players are trying to arrive at a split of the pie, with share α going to player 1 and 1 α going to player 2. It examines the ase where the potential agreements form a ontinuum, i.e., α [0, 1] and every one of those agreements is a Nash equilibrium for single-stage bargaining. This multipliity - that any agreement is possible - gives rise to the elebrated bilateral monopoly or bargaining problem, a problem that the pre-game theory generation of eonomists (inluding Edgeworth and Hiks) onsidered essentially indeterminate. The game-theoreti bargaining question then is: are there bargaining protools, modeled as non-ooperative games, that yield a unique equilibrium, a single agreement? To be sure, the first suh proposal that yielded a unique predition was set not in a non-ooperative framework but rather in a ooperative game; by Nash (1950) in his axiomati derivation of the well-known "Nash Solution." to the bargaining problem 1 The best known non-ooperative answer is Rubinstein (1982) who showed that if players take turns bargaining (with the player at time t either aepting the offer on the table or proposing an alternative share), then there is a unique subgame perfet equilibrium to the bargaining game. Moreover, when 1 The Nash Solution piks that share α for whih the produt of the two players payoffs is maximized. 1

the players disount fator approahes 1, then the unique equilibrium onverges to the Nash Solution. There is by now a large literature studying variations of the Rubinstein game. In this paper, we study two models and the first one, whih we all the Irreversible Agreements model, is a variation on Rubinstein. That model has the same alternating move struture, that a player at time t either aepts the existing offer or ounter-proposes. It also presumes that one an agreement is reahed, it annot be undone and a flow of payoffs orresponding to the agreement is reeived every period till the end of the game. 2 The one differene between our Irreversible Agreements model and Rubinstein s is that our agreement remains in fore for the remaining periods of a finite horizon whereas, in Rubinstein s ase, it remains in fore for the infinite future. Another differene is that we allow very general payoffs. The real departure from the literature though is our seond model, one of Reversible Agreements. This is a model of repeated bargaining, in muh the same sense in whih we have models of repeated oligopoly or repeated trade agreements. It aptures the idea that when two negotiators sit down to negotiate an agreement they do not always expet it to be the last suh negotiation. They believe that the agreement they are about to hammer out will last a ertain number of periods, say ζ, and they also know that yet another agreement will need to be negotiated thereafter (and, of ourse, that one might end up being idential to the urrent agreement). This feature of repeated bargaining is, we believe, pervasive. When the auto ompanies negotiate with unions they are aware that the agreements are short-term and a preursor to subsequent negotiations. When two ountries negotiate a bilateral trade or defense or industrial treaty, again those are typially short-term treaties. Pervasive as repeated bargaining is, best that we an tell, it has been ignored by the literature. This paper is a first step towards an analysis. As a first step, there are two modeling hoies that we make. First, we take the length of the urrent agreement ζ to be one, i.e., eah agreement, one reahed, lasts one period. This is easily generalized. Seond, the urrent agreement beomes - by assumption - the status quo option for the subsequent negotiation. Suppose that an agreement has been reahed at time t; player 1 responded to the offer on the table, 1 α for player 2, by agreeing to take share α. In the next period t + 1, this "move" of player 1, the share α then beomes the status quo proposal to whih player 2 has to respond. If he agrees to take 1 α, the agreement ontinues for one more period - with assoiated positive payoffs. Alternatively, if he responds with 1 α there is no longer an agreement in period t + 1 (and either way, the period t + 1 agreement proposal 1 α or the disagreement proposal, 1 α, is the offer on the table at period t + 2). And so on. That the agreement in period t forms the status quo for period t + 1 is one 2 The standard interpretation of the Rubinstein infinite horizon model is that play ends one agreement is reahed with a terminal payoff orresponding to the agreement. That, of ourse, is equivalent to saying that flow payoffs ontinue to be aumulated every one of the remaining periods at a rate that adds up to the terminal payoff. 2

way for the different periods or bargains to be linked through time. If t + 1 was a "fresh start" then, of ourse, the Irreversible Agreements model would be simply a sequene of Reversible Agreements models and the results of the latter would apply to the former. There are ertainly other modeling assumptions that ould link periods. Now to the results. In what follows let T stand for the game horizon. It should be lear that uniqueness results will only hold for T large. When T is small, we are likely to get multipliity sine we know, for example, that when T is one, we have an infinity of possible equilibria. Indeed, given that the agreements form a ontinuum, it should not surprise the reader that we will uniquely hoose from the ontinuum only when T. In what follows, an "equilibrium when T " should be understood to be the limit of equilibria for finite T. Furthermore, the ontinuum of agreements in the stage game will be assumed to define a Pareto frontier f that is downward sloping (sine a large share for player 1 is, by definition, a smaller share for player 2). In the Irreversible Agreements - or single bargain - model we prove three results, in eah ase when T. First, we show that as long as f is ontinous, there is a unique seletion, i.e., although there may be multiple shares that are equilibrium shares when T is finite, there is only one α that is the limiting share (of player 1). An example then shows that it is possible that this limit depends on whih player is the last to move. 3 Seond, if f is ontinuously differentiable, it must be the ase that eah of these two possible limits is a loal maximum for the produt of payoffs funtion, i.e., we must always get a loal Nash Solution. Third, if f is additionally, onave, then there is a unique limit and it orresponds to the global Nash Solution. We then turn to the Reversible Agreements - or multiple bargains - model. We first present two examples - first when the Pareto frontier is linear and seond when the Pareto frontier is irular. We show that when there are, say, τ periods left, the mover in that period will only aept agreements that give her intermediate payoffs, i.e., she will blok payoffs that are two low for her and will also blok payoffs that are too high for her. The first - bloking bad agreements - is also a feature of the Irreversible Agreements model. The interesting new feature with repeated bargaining is the seond - bloking agreements that are too good! In partiular, there are shares α 1 (τ) < α 2 (τ) - whih we ompute - suh that only agreements that lie in [α 1 (τ), α 2 (τ)] are aepted when there are τ periods left. Moreover, the aeptane region shrinks with the horizon length beause α 1 (τ + 1) α 1 (τ) and α 2 (τ + 1) α 2 (τ). In other words, the longer is the game horizon the less willing is a player to aept a deal. The reason why advantageous agreements are rejeted is that a player understands that the very good agreement might be short-lived. For instane, if player 1 aepts α > α 2 (τ + 1), she fears that the short-term high payoff would then be followed by a break-down in the agreement next period. Player 2, rather than take a 3 The player that is last to move aepts any share - when she finds herself in the last period. That, onsequently, puts her at a dis-advantage from a bargaining point of view. 3

ontinuane of low payoffs assoiated with the share 1 α would take a shortterm loss of payoffs - due to a disagreement - and instead look for the higher share implied by 1 α 1 (τ 1). So, ongoing intermediate payoffs are better than the "stop-start" of a high initial payoff followed by a long streth of low payoffs. The main theorem of the paper - and the general result of the seond model - then shows that what is shown by omputation in the examples is more broadly true. Provided f is ontinuously differentiable and onave, only intermediate agreements are equilibria. Furthermore, as T, the unique limit of the intermediate aeptane region is a singleton - and that singleton is again the Nash Solution. In other words, when T is large but finite, there ould possibly be multiple equilibrium agreements but they all have to be (arbitrarily) lose to the Nash Solution, fitting in ever more tightly around that solution as we take longer horizons. In Summary, alternating offer bargaining produes the Nash Solution as the unique outome and does so not only when there is a single bargain but even when there are multiple bargains. The astute reader will wonder why we have analyzed a finite horizon problem rather than an infinite horizon problem. The reason is that the infinite horizon would have a folk theorem and ertainly there would be no hane of a unique equilibrium seletion; indeed, the bargaining multipliity would dimensionally inrease sine not only would every agreement emerge as an equilibrium but so would dis-agreement outomes that are individually rational. That there is a folk theorem follows from the fat that any alternating move game is a stohasti game where the state variable at any time is the fixed ation of the non-mover. By the result of Dutta (1986) suh a stohasti game would have a folk theorem. 4 The other modeling detail is that, in this paper, we are onsidering a ontinuum of agreements. In a ompanion paper - Dutta and Takahashi (2012) - we have analyzed the ase where there are only a finite number of agreements. The advantage of the finite ase is that it is a little easier to understand in that setting why the Nash solution emerges in equilibrium. We explain that reasoning now. Consider the following stage game: 1\2 1 α 1 1 α 2 α 1 h 1, l 2 0, 0 α 2 0, 0 l 1, h 2 with h i > l i > 0 for i = 1, 2. We proeed by bakward indution. In the last period, it is a best response to aept whatever share is offered. Similarly, as long as there are only a few remaining periods. Things are different when the number of remaining periods 4 Stritly speaking, the Dutta (1986) result only applies when the state spae is finite whereas the state spae - the set of possible shares - in this setting is a ontinuum. However, at the risk of onsiderably heightened tehnial analysis, the Dutta result an be extended to this setting. 4

beomes larger than T i, where T i is defined as (T i 1)h i = T i l i or T i = h i /(h i l i ). Now, by bloking a bad agreement, and ounterproposing the better one, a player reeives a payoff of 0 in the urrent period but ontinues with payoffs of h i in the future, whereas by aepting a bad agreement, he reeives a payoff of l i in eah of the remaining periods. Suppose for example that T 1 > T 2. Then when the horizon inreases past T 2 player 2 rejets α 1. This leads to the equilibrium outome α 2, 1 α 2 whih favors player 2. Conversely, if T 1 < T 2. What determines T 1 T 2? Simple algebra shows that T 1 > T 2 if and only if l 1 h 2 > h 1 l 2, i.e., omparison between two Nash produts. 5 The Model is presented in Setion 2. In Setion 3 we present two examples to illustrate possible equilibria in the Irreversible Agreements model while in Setion 4 we present the three main results within that model. Setions 5 and 6 parallels that in the Reversible Agreements ase; Setion 5 presents two examples while Setion 6 presents the main theorem. Generalizations and extensions are olleted in Setion 7. 2 Model In this setion, we present two finite horizon bargaining models - one with irreversible agreements and the seond with reversible agreements. But first we disuss in some detail the bargaining stage game that we will fous on and the timing struture within whih we study that game. 2.1 Bargaining Stage Game Consider a two player bargaining environment in whih the players are trying to arrive at a split of the pie, with share α going to player 1 and 1 α going to player 2. Suppose that the potential agreements α form a ontinuum, i.e., α [0, 1]. Suppose further that x(α) represents the agreement payoff of player 1 whilst y(α) = f(x(α)) is the agreement payoff of player 2. (Frequently, we will suppress the argument α and simply write agreement payoffs as (x, f(x))). Players ations are "proposals" on shares. The following assumptions are made about this bargaining stage game: Definition The stage game is defined by strategy sets: player 1 an ask for a share α [0, 1] and player 2 an ask for a share 1 α [0, 1]. The asks are ompatible if α = α and we say then that there is an agreement. The asks are inompatible if α α and then we say that we have a disagreement. The following assumptions are made on the assoiated payoff s: 5 There are a number of knotty "integar problems" however that bedevil the finite agreements ase. For further details, see Dutta and Takahashi (2012). 5

1. disagreement strategy tuples have a onstant payoff (normalized to 0), i.e, the payoff to α, 1 α, where α α is (0,0); 2. eah agreement strategy tuple is a strit Nash equilibrium, i.e., whenever α = α, x( α) > 0 and f(x( α)) > 0; 3. the Pareto frontier is downward sloping, i.e., x(.) is stritly inreasing in α while f is stritly dereasing. An example will help larify the definition. Example 1 With x [0, 1] suppose that f(x) = 1 x. This is the linear bargaining problem that has been studied in many papers inluding (.) Here, α = x and so we an equivalently think of the hoie as being either x or α. In fat, given the monotoniity assumptions in 3. above, in general we an equivalently think of the hoie as being either of those variables. Within this model setion we will ontinue to talk of the hoie as being the share α. In the next setions, when we get to the analysis, we will often talk about the (diret) hoie of payoff x (by player 1 and y = f(x) by player 2). Obviously this bargaining problem - sometimes also referred to as the bilateral monopoly problem - has a ontinuum of equilibrium outomes when the stage game is played simultaneously by the two players; eah of the strategy tuples ( α, 1 α) is a Nash equilibrium with assoiated payoffs (x( α), f(x( α))). Hene, the (Nash) bargaining problem that arises is: whih of the agreements will emerge from strategi rational play? John Nash first proposed, in an axiomati derivation, the following (Nash bargaining) solution: 6 Definition The Nash bargaining solution in a bargaining stage game is the agreement x m, f(x m ) that maximizes the produt of the players payoffs, i.e., 7 x m f(x m ) = max x x.f(x) 2.2 Alternating Offers and Finite Horizon The multipliity of bargaining equilibria worsens if bargaining takes plae over many periods. If the same stage game is played simultaneously and repeatedly, i.e., an agreement is sought afresh every period, then the well-known folk theorems apply in both the infinite as well as the finite horizon versions. (Fudenberg and Maskin (1986) and Benoit and Krishna (1985).) Not only an agreements emerge then as equilibria but also periods of disagreements (sine every individually rational payoff an emerge as subgame perfet equilibrium payoff). 6 And subsequently as a limit solution to a lass of non-ooperative one period simultaneous bargaining games. See Nash (1950, 1953). 7 Note that in Nash s formulation what is maximized is the produt of net payoffs, where eah player s net payoff is the gross payoff less a status quo payoff. Here the status quo, or disagreement, payoff is zero. 6

Rubinstein (1982) was the first paper to ut through this indeterminay. He restrited attention to a single bargain, i.e., an attempt to find one agreement but did so in a model of alternating offers. He onsidered a model in whih in every period only one of the two players moves. She does so by responding to an offer that has been made in the previous period, an offer that speifies a share for the proposer. A response is a ounter-proposal that might or might not lead to an agreement. If the proposal is, say, α, the responder ould then say "yes" with a ounter-proposal of 1 α i.e., agree. On the other hand, the mover ould say "no" via a ounter-proposal of 1 α where α α, i.e., disagree, and that proposal would then beome the tabled offer for the subsequent period. In Rubinstein s model, whenever an agreement is reahed, the game ends with eah player reeiving the agreement payoffs. The above will be exatly the first of two models that we will study. We will all that the Irreversible Agreements model beause - one an agreement is reahed - it annot be undone. The one differene between our Irreversible Agreements model and Rubinstein s will be that our agreement will remain in fore for the remaining periods of a finite horizon whereas, in Rubinstein s ase, it remains in fore for the infinite future. 8 The seond model will be one in whih an agreement is in fore for the period in whih it is reahed but need not be in fore in subsequent period(s). In that model, if the ounter-proposal is 1 α then both players get agreement payoffs in that period. Next period, the mover responds to the existing (non-mover s) previous offer - 1 α. If she responds with α then the agreement ontinues for one more period - with assoiated positive payoffs. Alternatively, she is free to respond with α thereby olleting one period of zero disagreement payoffs but possibly moving play to a better - for her - agreement in the future. Sine we study finite horizon games that end after period T (< ) we will need, to begin with, a move onvention about who moves in the last period. One possibility is that it is player 1 who moves last and hene in the penultimate period it is player 2 who moves et. In other words, player 1 is the mover when there are an odd number of periods left whilst player 2 is the mover when there are an even number of periods left. An alternative onvention is to onsider the opposite possibility with player 2 being the mover when there is only one period left to go. It will be seen, that when there are very few periods of bargaining left, the hosen onvention will give asymmetri bargaining power to the player who does not move last. By looking at long enough bargaining periods, however, we will searh for equilibria where this onvention plays no role. If it does we will all suh an equilibria loal and if it does not we will all it global. (More below.) Lifetime payoffs will be evaluated aording to the (undisounted) average payoff; player i s evaluation of the payoff stream π i (a t, b t ), t = 1, 2,... T will 8 The standard interpretation of the Rubinstein infinite horizon model is that play ends with payoffs (x( α), f(x( α))). That, of ourse, is equivalent to saying that flow payoffs (1 δ)(x( α), f(x( α))) ontinue to be aumulated every one of the remaining infinite periods. (δ is the disount fator in the above.) 7

be given by 9 1 T T π i (a t, b t ) (1) t=1 One further speifiation that is required is how the game starts, i.e., what is the "initial state" of the game, the offer that is already on the table at the beginning of period 1. There are two standard ways to do this: one is to be agnosti and allow all possible initial states. A seond is to onsider a period 0 and allow the "mover" in that period to hoose the initial state (for period 1). Our results do not depend on whih of these speifiations is hosen. For onreteness, we will allow any possible initial state and will look for equilibris that are independent of the initial state. 2.3 Model 1 - Irreversible Agreements Definition: A bargaining game (with horizon T and stage game G) is said to have irreversible agreements if, starting with an off er α (respetively, 1 α), provided the ounter-offer is 1 α (respetively, α), i.e., if an agreement is reahed in period t, it then remains in fore for the remaining T t periods, i.e., the strategy tuple played in periods t, t + 1,...T is also given by ( α, 1 α) with assoiated payoff s x( α), f(x( α)) every period. Put differently, if an agreement is reahed, there is no further opportunity to make offers (and ounter-offers). In the sense that there is only one agreement, this model is essentially the finite horizon Rubinstein model. 2.4 Model 2 - Reversible Agreements The more dynami model is one of reversible agreements. Definition: A bargaining game (with horizon T and stage game G) is said to have reversible agreements if, when an offer α (respetively, 1 α) is made and followed by the agreement ounter-offer 1 α (respetively, α) in period t, it remains in fore for only that one period. In period t + 1, the aeptane offer of the other player, 1 α (respetively, α), beomes the offer to whih the responder in that subsequent period responds. Similarly, if the off er was not aepted in period t, then the ounter-offer onstitutes the offer to whih the responder in period t + 1 responds. Let us onsider some examples: Example 1 Agreement - Initially and Forever: Supose the initial state is α. Player 2, the mover in period 1 say, responds by playing 1 α. This onstitutes an agreement with assoiated positive payoffs in period 1. In period 2, the responding player, now player 1, piks α in response to the urrent offer of 1 α and the players earn the same payoff in period 2 as well. And this ontinues 9 Here a t = α for player 1 and b t = 1 α for player 2. Furthermore, π i (a t, b t) = x( α) or f(x( α)) respetively, if there is an agreement and equals 0 otherwise. Our analysis also applies to the ase of disounting, for any disount fator δ < 1. In that ase the appropriate 1 δ evaluation of lifetime payoffs is T 1 δ T t=1 δt 1 π i (a t). 8

till the end of the game garnering them total payoffs of T [x( α), f(x( α))] or per-period average payoffs of x( α), f(x( α)). Example 2 Disagreement Transiting to An Agreement: Again, supose the initial state is α. Player 2 responds by playing 1 α, α α. This onstitutes a disagreement with assoiated zero payoffs in period 1. However, player 2 might thereby have put on the table an offer whose agreement, if reahed, is far more favorable for her. There might follow a set of offers and ounter-offers none of them onstituting an agreement and so stage payoffs might remain zero. However, the series of rejetions might then narrow the set of potential agreements to something that is a better "ompromise" for both parties, say α. Under the twin pressures of finally getting an offer that is more reasonable for the responder - and that the end of the game is nearing - the two players might then reah the agreement α, 1 α for, say, the last T ζ periods. Note that both models are examples of dynami or stohasti games with the payoff-relevant state at time t being the fixed ation in that period (to whih the responder responds) and the number of remaining periods in the game. 2.5 Equilibrium - Global and Loal Convergene All ations are observable. Strategies, in both models, are hene defined in the usual way as history-dependent ation hoies. A t th period strategy for a mover in that period is a history-dependent (mixed) ation hoie and a omplete strategy is a speifiation for every move period (and after every history). A strategy vetor - one strategy for every player - defines in the usual way a (possibly probabilisti) ation hoie and hene an expeted payoff for the t th period for eah player. Sine the game has a finite horizon and sine this is a game of perfet information, Subgame Perfet Equilibrium (SPE) is determined via bakward indution in both models. When there is a single period left, the mover in that period, player 1 say, plays her best reponse; all that α (β, 1) where - heneforth - β = 1 α is the previous period proposal of player 2. Evidently, the two variables - the offer on the table β and the remaining number of periods, 1, is all that is payoff-relevant in seleting a best response. Similarly, at the penultimate period, the mover - player 2 - has a best response β (α, 2) based on the proposal on the table, α, the number of remaining periods, 2, and the best response funtion α (β, 1) that will govern the subsequent period s ation. In this fashion, we derive best response funtions for player 1, α (β, τ), whenever there are an odd number of periods τ remaining and best response funtions β (α, τ) for player 2 when τ is even. Note that in this perfet information setting optimal hoies are, typially, Markovian and unique. The only way that a mixed strategy SPE - or a history-dependent SPE - an arise is from ties in the mover s payoffs. 10 10 Note that in both models, the set of SPE payoffs is always history independent; the set of payoff vetors that an arise as a SPE in the subgame that starts at date t and a partiular history only depends on the urrent state, i.e., the offer on the table (and the number of remaining periods τ). 9

This paper will investigate properties the equilibrium hoie and value sets must satisfy, when τ is large. Towards that end, let us define the equilibrium agreements A (τ) = {α : β (α, τ) = 1 α}, τ even A (τ) = {α (β, τ) : β s.t. α (β, τ) = 1 β}, τ odd As should be lear from the definitions, A is the set of agreements that an arise from equilibrium play, either beause player 1 will agree to take that share - when τ is odd or beause that is a share that player 2 would be willing to give player 1 - when τ is even. Finally, define the limit A = τ A (τ) whenever it exists. In partiular, if the limit exists and is, furthermore, a singleton, then we shall say that the bargaining game has a unique equilibrium agreement for "long" horizons: Definition 2 The alternating move, finite horizon Irreversible Agreement game - respetively, Rreversible Agreement game - has a unique equilibrium if A is a singleton. Let A have a singleton and suppose it is α. It should be lear in the Irreversible Agreement game that, if the horizon is long enough, then the only initial proposals, that will get aepted (immediately and thereafter stay in plae by definition) are proposals in the neighborhood of α. The longer the horizon the smaller is that aeptane neighborhood. It should also be lear that even in the Reversible Agreement game that, if the horizon is long enough, then the only initial proposals, that will get aepted (immediately and thereafter stay in plae through equilibrium behavior) are proposals in the neighborhood of α. Again, the longer the horizon the smaller is that aeptane neighborhood. In this instane, these equilibria with agreements that are never broken, are, in prinipal, a subset of more ompliated equilibrium behavior that might involve, for instane, agreement-disgreement yles. We will omment on that in Setion 5. When we first defined the finite horizon game, we had two parameters - initial state and horizon length - and one onvention to speify - the last mover. In the definitions and arguments immediately above, we have found onepts where the two parameters ease to be relevant - sine the limit aeptane set is independent of them. However, we still have the onvention that the last mover be player 1. Clearly, an alternative onvention would be that the last mover is player 2. Everything that we have done so far an be re-ast in this parallel world: with one period to go, player 2 has a best response funtion β (α, 1) and based on that player 1 has a best response funtion with two periods to go α (β, 2). In this fashion, we derive best response funtions for player 1, α (β, τ), whenever there are an even number of periods τ remaining and best response funtions β (α, τ) for player 2 when τ is odd. 10

Finally, let us define the equilibrium agreements A (τ) = {α : β (α, τ) = 1 α}, τ odd A (τ) = {α (β, τ) : β s.t. α (β, τ) = 1 β}, τ even and the assoiated limit A = τ A (τ) whenever it exists. In partiular, if both limits exist and are, furthermore, singletons equal to eah other, then we shall say that the bargaining game has a unique global equilibrium agreement: Definition 3 The alternating move, finite horizon Irreversible Agreement game - respetively, Rreversible Agreement game - has a unique global equilibrium if A and A are singletons and A = A. 3 Irreversible Agreements: Examples of Global and Loal Convergene In this setion we provide two examples within Model 1, the model where agreement, one reahed, is irreversible. The first is an example where the Pareto frontier is linear and this example will exhibit global onvergene; regardless of whether it is player 1 or 2 who is the last mover, there is a unique agreement in the limit. In fat, in this example, the agreement is reahed within two periods. Moreover, that unique agreement is nothing but the Nash bargaining solution. The example will also illustrate an algorithm that will re-appear in a more general result whih is to be found in the next setion, a result that will apply to broader lasses of Pareto frontiers - beyond the linear - that have the property that the Nash produt x.f(x) is single-peaked. The seond example will be one in whih the Pareto frontier is piee-wise linear and onvex (i.e., kinked "inwards"). Consequently, the Nash produt will be multi-peaked. In this example, there will be loal onvergene but not global onvergene in that there will be two andidate limits, say α and α, α < α and whih of them is reahed will depend on whih player is the last mover. If player 1 is the last to move that puts her at a dis-advantage and onsequently the limit is α. On the other hand, if player 2 is the last to move that plaes greater bargaining power in the hands of player 1 and leads to an agreement α that is more advantageous for her. Furthermore, one of the two limts will be seen to be the Nash bargaining solution and the other will be seen to be a "loal" Nash bargaining solution, i.e., a loal maximizer of the Nash produt x.f(x). The example will also illustrate a more general result whih is to be found in the next setion. The general result will show that bargaining leads always to a loal Nash bargaining solution. 11

3.1 Linear Pareto Frontier Suppose that f(x) = mx +, m > 0, > 0 Note that argmax x xf(x) =. We will use this example to investigate global onvergene. In terms of the analysis, it will turn out to be easier to imagine that what eah player hooses is a payoff - rather than a share of the pie. For example, player 1 aepts all agreements that give her a ertain set of payoffs. Sine the payoff funtion x(α) is monotonially inreasing in the share α, it learly does not matter whether we have the player hoosing x or α. Similarly, for player 2 we will imagine that he hooses y = f(x) rather than the share 1 α that yields that payoff. Within this example, we will prove the following: Proposition 4 If f is linear, then there is global onvergene. Expliit omputation shows that the equilibrium strategies are of the form: there are payoff s x(τ) and x(τ), x(τ) < x(τ), that form the boundary of the (payoff ) agreement region. If it is player 1 s turn to move, with τ periods to go, she will only agree provided the proposal on the table gives her at least x(τ) as payoff. Similarly, if it is player 2 s turn to move, with τ periods to go, he will only agree provided the proposal on the table gives him at least f(x(τ)). Furthermore, x(τ) < < x(τ). Also, x(τ + 2) x(τ) for all τ odd. Similarly, x(τ + 2) x(τ) for all τ even. Finally, lim t x(τ) = lim t x(τ) = Reall that τ is the number of remaining periods and player 1 is the player who moves in the last period. As noted, x(τ) for τ = 1, 3, 5... denotes the (worst) agreement payoff that player 1 is willing to aept at those periods (and let the assoiated payoff for player 2 be denoted y(τ), i.e., y(τ) = f(x(τ))). Let y(τ) for τ = 2, 4, 6,... denote the worst agreement that player 2 will similarly aept when it is his turn to move. Let x(τ) = y(τ) m denote the assoiated payoff for player 1, i.e., that is the best agreement that player 2 will reeive in even periods. We will now ompute x(τ) and x(τ) and show that lim x(τ) = lim x(τ) = τ τ Hene, the state-independent SPE is the Nash solution. Proof. We will ompute the agreement regions. We start with τ = 1 It is easy to see that player 1 will agree to any share when there is a single period left beause agreement gives her a non-negarive payoff (and, in fat,a stritly positive payoff if the proposed share is positive). Hene, x(1) = 0 implying y(1) = τ = 2 With two periods to go, player 2 an guarantee himself y(1) = by turning down a proposal in this period and waiting for the next with a ounterproposal that gives him everything. Hene, the worst payoff that he will aept. 12

is given by the equality = 2y(2) implying that y(2) = 2 implying that x(2) = τ = 3 With three periods to go, player 1 an guarantee herself x(2) = by turning down a proposal on the table and waiting for her best payoff for two periods. Hene, the worst payoff that she will aept is given by the equality m = 3x(3) implying that x(3) = 1 3 m i.e., that y(3) = 2 3 τ = 4 Continuing in that fashion, y(4) an be derived from 2 = 4y(4) implying that y(4) = 2 implying that x(4) = τ = 5 Again, the worst payoff the mover, player 1, will take is given by 2 m = 5x(5) implying x(5) = 2 5 m implying y(5) = 3 5 τ = 6 3 = 6y(6) implying that y(6) = 2 implying that x(6) = 3 τ = 7 m = 7x(7) implying x(7) = 3 7 m implying y(7) = 4 7 τ = 8 4 = 8y(8) implying that y(8) = 2 implying that x(8) = 4 τ = 9 m = 9x(9) implying x(9) = 4 9 m implying y(9) = 5 9 τ = 10 5 = 10y(10) implying that y(10) = 2 It is lear that the odd-period worst agreement payoffs of player 1, x(τ) - after fatoring out the m - are 0, 1 3, 2 5, 3 7, 4 9,... n 1 2n + 1,... implying that x(10) = for n = 1, 2,.. Of ourse that sequene onverges to 1 2. It is also lear that the best payoffs of player 1, x(τ) = for all even numbered τ. Hene, the unique limit payoff for player 1 is, the Nash bargaining solution. Something that the astute reader would have already noted - and that will be useful in the sequel - is the following observation. In the odd periods, when it is player 1 s turn to move the lowest payoff that she will aept is given by the following equation τx(τ) = (τ 1)x(τ 1) and, similarly, in the even periods, the lowest payoff that player 2 would be willing to take is given by τf(x(τ)) = (τ 1)f(x(τ 1)) This equations will be extensively used in the general analysis that follows. Let us now turn to global onvergene - that the same limit would hold had we onsidered the ase in whih player 2 is the last mover. Easy omputation, again using equations above, tell us that the odd period payoffs of player 1, now x(τ), are - after fatoring out m - given by 1, 2 3, 3 5, 4 7, 5 9,... n 2n 1,... for n = 1, 2,.. Of ourse that sequene onverges to 1 2. It is also lear that the worst payoffs of player 1, x(τ) = for all even numbered τ. Hene, again, the unique limit payoff for player 1 is, the Nash bargaining solution and we have global onvergene. 13

3.2 Convex Pareto Frontier We turn now to a seond example. In this ase, the Pareto frontier will be pieewise linear and kinked "inwards" thereby reating a onvex frontier. Suppose that f(x) = 2x + 10, x 8 3 f(x) = 0.5x + 6, x 8 3 Note that the Nash produt. xf(x), is double-peaked, ahieveing a loal maximum in the left line-segment at 2.5 and another at 6 - whih is where it also ahieves the global maximum, i.e., argmax x xf(x) = 6. We will use this example to show - a) there need not be global onvergene, i.e., that the agreement that is eventually reahed might be different depending on whether it is player 1 or 2 who moves last but that, b) it must be a loal maximum of the Nash produt funtion. Proposition 5 Consider the onvex f example above. Expliit omputation shows that player 1 s equilibrium worst and best payoffs x(τ) and x(τ), x(τ) < x(τ), have the following property: lim t x(τ) = lim t x(τ) = 2.5 if player 1 is the last mover but lim t x(τ) = lim t x(τ) = 6 if, instead, player 2 is the last mover. So there is no global onvergene but there is saliene to the Nash produt funtion in that a) there is a limiting agreement and b) that limit has to be at least a loal maximum of the Nash produt funtion. Proof. As in the previous example, we will ompute the agreement regions. We start with τ = 1 Clearly, x(1) = 0 implying y(1) = 10. τ = 2 With two periods to go, sine player 2 an guarantee himself y(1) = 10 by turning down a proposal in this period, the worst payoff that he will aept is given by the equality 10 = 2y(2) implying that y(2) = 5 implying that x(2) = 2.5. τ = 3 With three periods to go, sine player 1 an guarantee herself x(2) = 2.5 by turning down a proposal on the table, the worst payoff that she will aept is given by the equality 5 = 3x(3) implying that x(3) = 5 3 i.e., that y(3) = 20 3. τ = 4 Continuing in that fashion, y(4) an be derived from 20 = 4y(4) implying that y(4) = 5 implying that x(4) = 2.5. τ = 5 Again, the worst payoff the mover, player 1, will take is given by 10 = 5x(5) implying x(5) = 2 implying y(5) = 6. τ = 6 30 = 6y(6) implying that y(6) = 5 implying that x(6) = 2.5. τ = 7 15 = 7x(7) implying x(7) = 15 40 7 implying y(7) = 7. τ = 8 40 = 8y(8) implying that y(8) = 5 implying that x(8) = 2.5. τ = 9 20 = 9x(9) implying x(9) = 20 50 9 implying y(9) = 9. τ = 10 50 = 10y(10) implying that y(10) = 5 implying that x(10) = 2.5. 14

τ = 11 25 = 11x(11) implying x(11) = 25 11 It is lear that the odd-period worst agreement payoffs of player 1 are 0, 5 3, 10 5, 15 7, 20 9, 25 1)...5(n 11 2n 1,... for n = 1, 2,.. Of ourse that sequene onverges to 2.5. It is also lear that the best payoffs of player 1, x(τ) = 2.5 for all even numbered τ. Hene, the unique limit payoff for player 1 is 2.5, whih is a loal maximum for the Nash produt funtion but not the Nash bargaining solution. Let us now turn to the limit that would hold had we onsidered the ase in whih player 2 is the last mover. Easy omputation, again using equations above, tell us that the odd period payoffs of player 1, now x(τ), are given by 12 1, 24 3, 36 5, 48 7,... 12n 2n 1,... for n = 1, 2,.. Of ourse that sequene onverges to 6. It is also eaasily shown that the worst payoffs of player 1, x(τ) = 6 for all even numbered τ. Hene, again, the unique limit payoff for player 1 is 6, and this is the Nash bargaining solution. To summarize, in this example, there are two loal maxima of the Nash produt funtion. The one that is preferred by player 1 is approahed if player 2 is the last to move - and vie-versa. However, those are the only possible equilibrium agreements. 4 Irreversible Agreements: Results on Global and Loal Convergene In this setion we provide results on onvergene, i.e., unique seletion of a bargaining agreement. There are three results. The first says that as long as f is ontinous, then the sequenes of best and worst agreement, x(τ) and x(τ) must onverge regardless of whether player 1 or player 2 is the last to move. Call the limit when player 1 is the last to move x and that when player 2 is the last to move x. Note that in the two examples of the previous setion we were able to ompute these limits diretly. The first result of this setion will therefore establish that - even when they are not omputable - they must exist. The seond result says that both x and x have to be loal maxima of the Nash produt funtion x.f(x) as long as f is known to be ontinously differentiable. This was illustrated by the seond example of the previous setion. An immediate orollary of that result is that when the Nash produt is singlepeaked - for example if f is onave - then the two limits have to oinide and be the Nash bargaining solution. This was illustrated by what we omputed when the Pareto frontier, f, is linear in the first example of the previous setion. 15

4.1 Convergene Theorem 6 Suppose that f is ontinuous. Then, there is a limit to the best and worst agreements of player 1, x(τ) and x(τ), and the two limits oinide. This is true regardless of whether player 1 is the last to move or player 2. Proof. As we have seen above, the two sequenes are derived via the following equations x(τ + 1) = τ τ + 1 x(τ), f(x(τ + 1)) = τ τ + 1 f(x(τ)). From the first equation above it follows that τ + 2 1 x(τ + 2) = f τ + 1 ( τ τ + 1 f(x(τ)) ) Reall that the sequene x(.) is defined with intervals of 2,; if player 1 is the last to move then it is of the form x(1), x(3),... x(τ), x(τ + 2)... for all odd τ while it is of the form x(2), x(4),...x(τ), x(τ + 2)... for all even τ when player 2 is the last to move. We will now show that in both ases this sequene is onvergent. It is learly a sequene drawn from a ompat set and hene has a limit on a subsequene, say τ n, and all the subsequential limit x. On that subsequene, using the equation above, we must have lim t n x(τ n + 2) = x given the ontinuity of f. Sine for every onvergent subsequent it follows that the subsequene formed by the elements τ n + 2 onverge to the same limit, it must be the ase that the original sequene itself onverges to x. Evidently this argument shows that there is a limit regardless of whether we take the odd sequene or the even one, though the two limits need not be the same. Call them, as above, x and x respetively. Note also that f(x(τ + 1)) = τ τ + 1 f(x(τ)) and from that it follows that the sequene x(τ) must itself have a limit and that limit must be the same as that for x(τ + 1). 4.2 Loal Convergene Theorem 7 Suppose that f is ontinuously diff erentiable and furthermore that < f < 0. Then, the two limits x and x must both be loal maxima of the Nash produt funtion x.f(x). 16

Proof. By eliminating x( ) in the equation above we have ( ) τ + 2 f x(τ + 2) = τ f(x(τ)). (2) τ + 1 τ + 1 Given the assumptions on f, 11 and onsidering one of the limits, say x, what we know is that in a small enough neighborhood of x, if x < x, then xf (x) + f(x) > 0; if x > x, then xf (x) + f(x) < 0. Notie that x(τ + 2) x(τ) = O(1/τ). Thus, by linearizing (2), we have f(x(τ))+(x(τ+2) x(τ))f (x(τ))+ x(τ + 2)f (x(τ)) τ i.e., x(τ + 2) x(τ) = x(τ)f (x(τ)) + f(x(τ)) τf (x(τ)) = f(x(τ)) f(x(τ)) +O τ ( 1 τ 2 ( ) 1 + O τ 2. (3) Fix any ε > 0. Then for suffi iently large τ, x(τ +2) x(τ) < ε. Given that f is ontinuously differentiable and bounded above it follows that x(τ)f (x(τ))+ f(x(τ)) is arbitrarily small. Running ε 0 we an onlude that x must be a loal maximum of the Nash produt funtion x.f(x ). Clearly this argument holds for any limit point of x(τ) and, in partiular, for x. 4.3 Global Convergene Theorem 8 Suppose that f is ontinuously differentiable, that < f < 0 and furthermore that x.f(x) is single-peaked. Then, the two limits x and x oinide at the global maxima of the Nash produt funtion x.f(x), i.e., equilibrium play uniquely selets the Nash bargaining solution. Proof. The proof follows as an immediate orollary of the result in the previous sub-setion. When f is single-peaked it has, by assumption, only one (loal/global) maxima. Hene, the two limits x and x oinide at the global maximum whih is, again from the definition, the Nash bargaining solution. Remark 9 A suffi ient ondition for single-peakedness of the Nash produt funtion is when f is onave. Hene, we have found the general result for the linear Pareto frontier ase whose equilibrium was omputed in the previous setion. ), 11 The following may not be the weakest possible assumptions. Say, ontinuous differentiability might be relaxed to mere differentiability, et. 17

5 Reversible Agreements: Two Examples of Global Convergene In this setion we swith to Model 2 - the Reversible Agreements model - in whih an agreement one reahed is only good for that period. In the subsequent period, the player who then has the mover an over-turn the agreement by proposing a different split of the pie. He would, of ourse, suffer the short-term payoff onsequene of zero disagreement payoffs but might wish to trade that in for a more attrative payoff in the future. On the fae of it, it would appear that equiibrium behavior ould be easelessly omplex. Agreements might appear, last for a bit, and then be replaed by other agreements. Or there might be long periods of time over whih there is simply a tug and fro of bargains between the two players with no agreements reahed. We start by providing two examples where the behavior is remarkably ordered. The first is a return to our initial example where the Pareto frontier is linear. Within this example we will exhibit that yet again there is global onvergene; regardless of whether it is player 1 or 2 who is the last mover, there is a unique agreement in the limit. In fat, in this example, the agreement sets will turn out to be idential to those in the Irreversible ase! Consider the ase where player 1 is the last to move. Reall that there are worst payoff agreements for her, x(τ), for τ = 1, 3, 5...; with odd number of periods τ left, player 1 is willing to aept any agreement that gives her a payoff of at least x(τ). Similarly there are best payoff agreements for player 1, x(τ), for τ = 2, 4, 6...; with even number of periods τ left, player 2 is willing to aept any agreement that gives him a payoff of at least f(x(τ)), or x(τ), for τ = 2, 4, 6... is the most that player 1 an hope to ahieve. It turns out in the examples that follow that there is two-sided bloking - when there are an odd number of periods left to play, player 1 will aept any agreement that gives her a payoff of at least x(τ) but no more than x(τ 1). The seond part is the new phenomenon; even if player 1 is onfronted with a partiularly attrative proposal - one that gives her more than x(τ 1) - she will say, no thank you! As will beome lear, this antiipatory blok is instigated from knowing that suh an agreement is very short-term, will be over-turned next period, and when it is over-turned will be replaed by a onsiderably worse agreement. The seond example will show that the above result is not an artfat of risk-neutrality. In it we will onsider a (quarter) irle - and hene onave - Pareto frontier. In this example, there will again be global onvergene; again, a player will blok not only agreements that are dis-advantageous for her but also agreements that are too good. 12 In both examples, the set of agreements will onverge uniquely and globally 12 Indeed, this example, like the linear example, generates idential sequenes x(τ) and x(τ) in both the Irreversible and Reversible models. The only differene is that in the Irreversible model, player 1 bloks anything below x(τ) while in the Reversible model she also bloks anything above x(τ 1). Similarly, player 2 only bloks anything below f(x(τ)) in the Irreversible model but additionally bloks every agreement that gives him above f(x(τ 1)) in the Reversible ase. 18

to the Nash bargaining solution, i.e., the unique maximizer of the Nash produt x.f(x). These example will also illustrate a more general result whih is to be found in the next setion. The general result will show that Reversible Agreement bargaining leads always to the Nash bargaining solution if f is onave. 5.1 Linear Pareto Frontier Suppose that f(x) = mx +, m > 0, > 0. Note again that argmax x xf(x) = Let us start with the ase where player 1 is the last to move. As before, x(τ) for τ = 1, 3, 5... will denote the (worst) agreement payoff that player 1 is willing to aept at those periods (and let the assoiated payoff for player 2 be denoted y(τ), i.e., y(τ) = f(x(τ))). Let y(τ) for τ = 2, 4, 6,... denote the worst agreement that player 2 will similarly aept when it is his turn to move. Let x(τ) = y(τ) denote the assoiated payoff for player m 1. These will be omputed in exatly the same fashion as in the Irreversible Agreement ase and will have the exat same values. We will then show that player 1 - when it is her turn to move - will aept any agreement between x(τ) and x(τ 1) and we will, without loss write x(τ) = x(τ 1). We will also show that player 2 - when it is his turn to move - will aept any agreement between y(τ) and y(τ 1) and we will, without loss write y(τ) = y(τ 1). In other words, when it is player 2 s move, player 1 s payoffs will again be nested within x(τ) and x(τ). We already know that lim x(τ) = lim x(τ) = τ τ and hene, even in this ase, the limiting SPE will turn out to be the Nash bargaining solution. τ = 1 With one period to go, player 1 will aept anything, i.e. the lowest payoff she will take x(1) = 0. At the same time there is no payoff that she will deem too good and refuse, i.e., x(1) = m. Hene, x(1) = 0, x(1) = m with assoiated payoffs of player 2 y(1) = and y(1) = 0 respetively. τ = 2 With two periods to go, player 2 an guarantee himself y(1) = by turning down a proposal in this period and waiting for the next with a ounterproposal that gives him everything. Hene, the worst payoff that he will aept is given by the equality = 2y(2) implying that y(2) = 2 implying that x(2) = Additionally, sine player 1 does not blok anything in the subsequent. period, he has no reason to blok any agreements that give him too muh, i.e., y(1) = and hene x(1) = 0. Colleting all this we have, x(2) = 0, x(2) =. τ = 3 With three periods to go, player 1 an guarantee herself x(2) = by turning down a proposal on the table and waiting for her best payoff for two periods. Hene, the worst payoff that she will aept is given by the equality m = 3x(3) implying that x(3) = 1 3 m i.e., that y(3) = 2 3. Additionally, if 19