Complexity of Iterated Dominance and a New Definition of Eliminability

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Complexity of Iterated Dominance and a New Definition of Eliminability"

Transcription

1 Complexity of Iterated Dominance and a New Definition of Eliminability Vincent Conitzer and Tuomas Sandholm Carnegie Mellon University 5000 Forbes Avenue Pittsburgh, PA {conitzer, sandholm}@cs.cmu.edu April 8, 2004 Abstract While the Nash equilibrium solution concept is studied more and more intensely in our community, the perhaps more elementary concept of iterated dominance has received much less attention. This paper makes two main contributions. First, we prove some basic complexity results about iterated dominance. We show that determining whether there is some path that eliminates a given strategy is NP-complete with weak dominance. This allows us to also show that determining whether there is a path that leads to a unique solution is NP-complete. Both of these results hold regardless of whether dominance by mixed strategies is allowed. (The second result was already known for the case of dominance by pure strategies only, in a slightly less restricted setting [4].) As our second contribution, we present a new definition of elimination of strategies, and show that it spans a spectrum of solution concepts from strict dominance to Nash equilibrium. We point out that checking whether a strategy is eliminable relative to the sets of all strategies is conp-complete under this definition. 1 Introduction In settings with self-interested agents, the optimal action for one agent may depend on the actions taken by other agents. In such settings, the agents require tools from game theory to rationally decide on an action. Game theory offers various formal models of strategic settings (the best-known of which is a game in normal (or matrix) form, specifying a payoff (utility) for each agent for each combination of strategies that the agents choose), as well as solution concepts, which, given a game, specify which outcomes are reasonable (under various assumptions of rationality and common knowledge). Probably the best-known (and, in our community, certainly the most-studied) solution concept is that of Nash equilibrium. A Nash equilibrium specifies a strategy for each player, in such a way that no player has an incentive to (unilaterally) deviate from 1

2 the prescribed strategy. The complexity of constructing a Nash equilibrium in matrix games has been labeled one of the two most important open problems on the boundary of P today [8]. The best-known algorithm for computing a Nash equilibrium, the Lemke-Howson algorithm [5], has a worst-case exponential running time [9]. Perhaps surprisingly, the more elementary solution concepts of dominance and iterated dominance have received much less attention in the computer science community. (The main computational study of these concepts has taken place in a paper in the game theory community [4].) A strategy strictly dominates another strategy if it performs strictly better against all opponent strategies, and weakly dominates it if it performs at least as well against all opponent strategies, and strictly better against at least one. The idea is that dominated strategies can be eliminated from consideration. In iterated dominance, the elimination proceeds in rounds, and becomes easier as more strategies are eliminated: in any given round, the dominating strategy no longer needs to perform better than or as well as the dominated strategy against opponent strategies that were eliminated in earlier rounds. One of the main reasons that these solution concepts have received less attention is the fact that they are often too strong, in the following sense. Oftentimes it is not the case that all but one strategy can be eliminated this way for each player, and thus there is no solution (consisting of a single strategy for each player) that is consistent with the concept. 1 In contrast, a Nash equilibrium always exists in finite games when mixed strategies (probability distributions over pure strategies) are allowed [7]. Unfortunately, the Nash equilibrium concept is often too weak: typically multiple Nash equilibria exist. The problem of equilibrium selection is a major one: in general, if the players are choosing their strategy according to different Nash equilibria, the result is not a Nash equilibrium. 2 Another interpretation of this is that the two solution concepts ((iterated) dominance and Nash equilibrium) actually suffer from the same problem: multiple strategies for a player may be consistent with it (because none of them can be dominated, or all of them occur in some Nash equilibrium). Ideally, we would have a sensible solution concept that prescribes a single solution for every game, but such a concept has eluded game theorists to this day. In this paper, we study some fundamental complexity questions concerning iterated dominance. We also propose a new elimination concept that, in terms of how powerful it is in eliminating strategies, spans a spectrum from strict dominance to Nash equilibrium. 2 Definitions In this section, we briefly review dominance and iterated dominance. Player i s strategy σ i is said to be strictly dominated by player i s strategy σ i if for any vector of strategies σ i for the other players, u i (σ i,σ i ) >u i (σ i,σ i). The definition is the same for weak dominance, except the inequality is not required to be strict but it should be strict for at least one vector σ i (so that two strategies cannot dominate each other). In this definition, it is sometimes allowed for σ i to be a mixed strategy (probability distribution over pure strategies), in which case the associated payoffs are the expected payoffs. For the purposes of this definition, the other players ( i) can be thought of as a single player. In iterated dominance, dominated strategies are eliminated, and no longer have any 1 Perhaps the one place where dominance is often studied is in the mechanism design literature, where the objective is to design the game itself. The freedom to design the game typically makes it possible to ensure that the game can be solved by dominance. 2 An exception is the case of two-player zero-sum games, where one player s loss is always the other s gain. Here, any combination of Nash equilibrium strategies (in this context also known as maximin strategies) is a Nash equilibrium. 2

3 effect on future dominance relations. For example, σ 1 may originally not dominate σ 1 because the latter performs better against σ 2; but then, once σ 2 is eliminated because it is dominated by σ 2, σ 1 dominates σ 1, and the latter can be eliminated. Either strict or weak dominance can be used in this definition. More detailed discussions and examples can be found in standard texts on game theory or microeconomics [2, 6]. 3 Complexity of iterated dominance We now move on to iterated dominance. It is well-known that iterated strict dominance is path-independent (in the end the remaining strategies will be the same regardless of the order in which strategies are eliminated), and the elimination procedure can be executed in polynomial time (even when dominance by mixed strategies is allowed, because a simple linear program can be set up to determine whether a given strategy is dominated). In contrast, iterated weak dominance is path-dependent, and here we will investigate two questions: whether a given strategy is eliminated in some path, and whether there is a path to a unique solution. Definition 1 Given a game in matrix form and a distinguished strategy σ, IWD- STRATEGY-ELIMINATION asks whether there is some path of iterated weak dominance that eliminates σ. Given a game in matrix form, IWD-UNIQUE-SOLUTION asks whether there is some path of iterated weak dominance that leads to a unique solution (one strategy left per player). The following lemma shows a special case in which allowing for weak dominance by mixed strategies does not help. We will prove our hardness results in this setting, so that they will hold whether or not dominance by mixed strategies is allowed. Lemma 1 Suppose the only payoffs in a game are {0, 1}. Then every pure strategy that is weakly dominated by a mixed strategy is also weakly dominated by a pure strategy. Proof: Suppose pure strategy σ is weakly dominated by mixed strategy σ.ifσgets a payoff of 1 against some opponent strategy (or vector of opponent strategies if there are more than 2 players), then all the pure strategies that σ places positive probability on must also get a payoff of 1 against that opponent strategy (or else the expected payoff would be smaller than 1). Moreover, at least one of the pure strategies that σ places positive probability on must get a payoff of 1 against an opponent strategy that σ gets 0 against (or else the inequality would never be strict). It follows that this pure strategy weakly dominates σ. We are now ready to prove the main results of this section. Theorem 1 IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION is NP-complete, even with 2 players, and with 0 and 1 being the only utilities occurring in the matrix whether or not dominance by mixed strategies is allowed. Proof: The problem is in NP because given a sequence of strategies to be eliminated, we can easily check whether this is a valid sequence of eliminations (even when dominance by mixed strategies is allowed, because a simple linear program can be set up to determine whether a given strategy is dominated). To show that the problem is NP-hard, we reduce an arbitrary SAT instance (given by a nonempty set of clauses C over a nonempty set of variables V, with corresponding literals L = {+v : v V } { v :v V}) to the following IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION instance. (In this instance, we will specify that certain strategies are uneliminable. A strategy σ r 3

4 can be made uneliminable, even when 0 and 1 are the only allowed payoffs, by adding another strategy σ r and another opponent strategy σ c, so that: 1. σ r and σ r are the only strategies that give the row player a utility of 1 against σ c.2.σ r and σ r always give the row player the same utility. 3. σ c is the only strategy that gives the column player a utility of 1 against σ r, but otherwise σ c always gives the column player utility 0. This makes it impossible to eliminate any of these three strategies. We will not explicitly specify the additional strategies to make the proof more legible.) In this proof, we will denote row player strategies by s, and column player strategies by t, to improve legibility. Let the row player s pure strategy set be given as follows. For every variable v V, the row player has corresponding strategies s 1 +v,s 2 +v,s 1 v,s 2 v. Additionally, the row player has the following 2 strategies: s 1 0 and s 2 0, where s 2 0 = σ r (that is, it is the strategy we seek to eliminate). Finally, for every clause c C, the row player has corresponding strategies s 1 c (uneliminable) and s 2 c. Let the column player s pure strategy set be given as follows. For every variable v V, the column player has a corresponding strategy t v. For every clause c C, the column player has a corresponding strategy t c, and additionally, for every literal l L that occurs in c, a strategy t c,l. The column player has a single additional strategy t 1. For every variable v V, the column player has corresponding strategies t +v,t v (both uneliminable). Finally, the column player has two strategies t 1 0 (uneliminable) and t 2 0. The utility function for the row player is given as follows: u r (s 2 +v,t v )=1for all v V ; u r (s 1 v,t v )=1for all v V ; u r (s 1 +v,t 1 )=1for all v V ; u r (s 2 v,t 1 )=1for all v V ; u r (s b +v,t +v )=1for all v V and b {1,2}; u r (s b v,t v )=1for all v V and b {1,2}; u r (s 2 0,t c )=1for all c C; u r (s b 0,t 1 0)=1for all b {1,2}; u r (s 1 0,t 2 0)=1; and the row player s utility is 0 in every other case. The utility function for the column player is given as follows: u c (s 2 l,t c)=1for all c C and l L where l c (literal l occurs in clause c); u c (s 2 l 2,t c,l1 )=1for all c C and l 1,l 2 L, l 1 l 2 where l 2 c; u c (s 1 c,t c )=1for all c C; u c (s b c,t c,l )=1for all c C, l L, and b {1,2}; and the column player s utility is 0 in every other case. We now show the two instances are equivalent. First, suppose there is a solution to the SAT instance: that is, a truth-value assignment to the variables in V such that all clauses are satisfied. Then, consider the following sequence of eliminations in our game: 1. For every variable v that is set to true in the assignment, eliminate t v (which gives the column player utility 0 everywhere). 2. Then, for every variable v that is set to true in the assignment, eliminate s 2 +v using s 1 +v (which is possible because t v has been eliminated, and because t 1 has not been eliminated (yet)). 3. Now eliminate t 1 (which gives the column player utility 0 everywhere). 4. Next, for every variable v that is set to false in the assignment, eliminate s 2 v using s 1 v (which is possible because t 1 has been eliminated, and because t v has not been eliminated (yet)). 5. For every clause c which has the variable corresponding to one of its positive literals l =+vset to true in the assignment, eliminate t c using t c,l (which is possible because s 2 l has been eliminated, and s2 c has not been eliminated (yet)). 6. For every clause c which has the variable corresponding to one of its negative literals l = v set to false in the assignment, eliminate t c using t c,l (which is possible 4

5 because s 2 l has been eliminated, and s2 c has not been eliminated (yet)). 7. Because the assignment satisfied the formula, all the t c have now been eliminated. Thus, we can eliminate s 2 0 = σr using s 1 0. It follows that there is a solution to the IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION instance. Now suppose there is a solution to the IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION instance. By Lemma 1, we can assume that all the dominances are by pure strategies. We first observe that only s 1 0 can eliminate s 2 0 = σr, because it is the only other strategy that gets the row player a utility of 1 against t 1 0, and t 1 0 is uneliminable. However, because s 2 0 performs better than s 1 0 against the t c strategies, it follows that all of the t c strategies must be eliminated. For each c C, the strategy t c can only be eliminated by one of the strategies t c,l (with the same c), because these are the only other strategies that get the column player a utility of 1 against s 1 c, and s 1 c is uneliminable. But, in order for some t c,l to eliminate t c, s 2 l must be eliminated first. Only s 1 l can eliminate s 2 l, because it is the only other strategy that gets the row player a utility of 1 against t l, and t l is uneliminable. We next show that for every v V only one of s 2 +v,s 2 v can be eliminated. This is because in order for s 1 +v to eliminate s 2 +v, t v needs to have been eliminated and t 1, not (so t v must be eliminated before t 1 ); but in order for s 1 v to eliminate s 2 v, t 1 needs to have been eliminated and t v, not (so t 1 must be eliminated before t v ). So, set v to true if s 2 +v is eliminated, and to false otherwise Because by the above, for every clause c, one of the s 2 l with l c must be eliminated, it follows that this is a satisfying assignment to the SAT instance. Using Theorem 1, it is now (relatively) easy to show that IWD-UNIQUE-SOLUTION is also NP-complete. Theorem 2 IWD-UNIQUE-SOLUTION is NP-complete, even with 2 players, and with 0 and 1 being the only utilities occurring in the matrix whether or not dominance by mixed strategies is allowed. Proof: Again, the problem is in NP because we can nondeterministically choose the sequence of eliminations and verify whether it is correct. To show NP-hardness, we reduce an arbitrary IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION instance to the following IWD- UNIQUE-SOLUTION instance. Let all the strategies for each player from the original instance remain part of the new instance, and let the payoffs resulting from the players playing a pair of these strategies be the same. We add three additional strategies σ 1 r,σ 2 r,σ 3 r for the row player, and three additional strategies σ 1 c,σ 2 c,σ 3 c for the column player. Let the additional payoffs be as follows: u r (σ r,σ j c)=1for all σ r / {σ 1 r,σ 2 r,σ 3 r}and j {2,3}; u r (σ i r,σ c )=1for all i {1,2,3}and σ c / {σ 2 c,σ 3 c}; u r (σ i r,σ 2 c)=1for all i {2,3}; u r (σ 1 r,σ 3 c)=1; and the row player s utility is 0 in all other cases involving a new strategy. u c (σ 3 r,σ c )=1for all σ c / {σ 1 c,σ 2 c,σ 3 c}; u c (σ r,σ j c)=1for all j {2,3}(σ r is the strategy to be eliminated in the original instance); u c (σ i r,σ 1 c)=1for all i {1,2}; u r (σ 1 r,σ 2 c)=1; u r (σ 2 r,σ 3 c)=1; and the column player s utility is 0 in all other cases involving a new strategy. We proceed to show the two instances are equivalent. First suppose there exists a solution to the original IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION instance. Then, perform the same sequence of eliminations to eliminate σ r in the new IWD-UNIQUE-SOLUTION instance. (This is possible because at any stage, any weak 5

6 dominance for the row player in the original instance is still a weak dominance in the new instance, because the two strategies payoffs for the row player are the same when the column player plays one of the new strategies; and the same is true for the column player.) Once σ r is eliminated, let σ 1 c eliminate σ 2 c. (It performs better against σ 2 r.) Then, let σ 1 r eliminate all the other remaining strategies for the row player. (It always performs better against either σ 1 c or σ 3 c.) Finally, σ 1 c is the unique best response against σ 1 r among the column player s remaining strategies, so let it eliminate all the other remaining strategies for the column player. Thus, there exists a solution to the IWD-UNIQUE-SOLUTION instance. Now suppose there exists a solution to the IWD-UNIQUE-SOLUTION instance. By Lemma 1, we can assume that all the dominances are by pure strategies. We will show that none of the new strategies (σ 1 r,σ 2 r,σ 3 r,σ 1 c,σ 2 c,σ 3 c) can either eliminate another strategy, or be eliminated before σ r is eliminated. Thus, there must be a sequence of eliminations ending in the elimination of σ r, which does not involve any of the new strategies, and is therefore a valid sequence of eliminations in the original game (because all original strategies perform the same against each new strategy). We now show that this is true by exhausting all possibilities for the first elimination before σ r is eliminated that involves a new strategy. None of the σ i r can be eliminated by a σ r / {σ 1 r,σ 2 r,σ 3 r}, because the σ i r perform better against σ 1 c. σ 1 r cannot eliminate any other strategy, because it always performs poorer against σ 2 c. σ 2 r and σ 3 r are equivalent from the row player s perspective (and thus cannot eliminate each other), and cannot eliminate any other strategy because they always perform poorer against σ 3 c. None of the σ j c can be eliminated by a σ c / {σ 1 c,σ 2 c,σ 3 c}, because the σ j c always perform better against either σ 1 r or σ 2 r. σ 1 c cannot eliminate any other strategy, because it always performs poorer against either σ r or σ 3 r. σ 2 c cannot eliminate any other strategy, because it always performs poorer against σ 2 r or σ 3 r. σ 3 c cannot eliminate any other strategy, because it always performs poorer against σ 1 r or σ 3 r. Thus, there exists a solution to the IWD-STRATEGY-ELIMINATION instance. A slightly weaker version of the part of Theorem 2 concerning dominance by pure strategies only is the main result by Gilboa, Kalai, and Zemel [4]. 3 4 A new concept of eliminability The concept of (iterated) dominance is often too strong (it cannot eliminate enough strategies). But, if possible, we would like a stronger argument for choosing a strategy (or eliminating another strategy) than Nash equilibrium. Hence, it would be desirable to have a solution concept that is inbetween the two in strength. In this section, we will provide such a concept. In fact, our concept spans an entire spectrum of strength between Nash equilibrium and strict dominance, and in the extremes can be made to coincide with either of these two solution concepts. We will think of a concept as stronger if it can eliminate fewer strategies. We would expect this to mean (presuming that the concept is sensible) that if a strategy can be eliminated with a stronger concept, this is a stronger argument that the strategy should not be played. Also, with a stronger concept it is more difficult to eliminate everything but a single solution; so if a solution can still be obtained this way, it presumably satisfies the criteria of weaker concepts as well. 4 3 Besides not proving the result for dominance by mixed strategies, the original result was weaker because it required payoffs {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8} rather than just {0, 1} (so our Lemma 1 canot be applied to it to get the result for mixed strategies). 4 Admittedly, this concept of strength remains a bit counterintuitive in some cases; for instance, it may be tempting to say that Nash equilibrium is a more powerful concept than (iterated) dominance because it is able to eliminate more strategies from consideration. The reader is advised to be careful. 6

7 4.1 Example Because the definition of our concept is complex, we will first illustrate it with an example. Consider the following (partially specified) game. σc 1 σc 2 σc 3 σc 4 σr 1?,??, 2?, 0?, 0 σr 2 2,? 2, 2 2, 0 2, 0 σr 3 0,? 0, 2 3, 0 0, 3 σr 4 0,? 0, 2 0, 3 3, 0 A quick look at this game reveals that strategies σr 3 and σr 4 are both almost dominated by σr but 2 they perform better than σr 2 on σc 3 and σc 4, respectively. Similarly, strategies σc 3 and σc 4 are both almost dominated by σc 2 but they perform better than σc 2 on σr 4 and σc 3, respectively. So we are unable to eliminate any strategies using (even weak) dominance. Now consider the following reasoning. In order for it to be worth it for the row player to ever play σr 3 rather than σr, 2 the column player should play σc 3 at least 2 3 of the time. (If it is exactly 2 3, then switching from σ2 r to σr 3 will cost the row player 2 exactly 1 3 of the time, but the row player will gain 1 exactly 2 3 of the time, so the expected benefit is 0.) But, similarly, in order for it to be worth it for the column player to ever play σc 3, the row player should play σr 4 at least 2 3 of the time. But again, in order for it to be worth it for the row player to ever play σr, 4 the column player should play σc 4 at least 2 3 of the time. Thus, if both the row and column player accurately assess the probability that the other places on these strategies, and their strategies are rational with respect to these assessments (as would be the case in a Nash equilibrium); then, if the row player puts positive probability on σr, 3 by the previous reasoning, the column player should be playing σc 3 at least 2 3 of the time, and σ4 c at least 2 3 of the time. Of course, this is impossible; so, in a sense, the row player should not be playing σr. 3 It may appear that all we have shown is that σr 3 is not played in any Nash equilibrium. But, to some extent, our argument for not playing σr 3 did not make use of the full elimination power of the Nash equilibrium concept. Most notably, we only reasoned about a small part of the game: we never mentioned strategies σr 1 and σc 1, and we did not even specify most of the payoffs for these strategies. (It is easy to extend this example so that our argument only uses an arbitrarily small fraction of the strategies and of the payoffs in the matrix, for instance by adding many copies of σr 1 and σc 1.) The locality of the reasoning is more akin to the notion of dominance, which is perhaps the extreme case of local reasoning only two strategies are mentioned in it. So, in this sense, our argument is somewhere inbetween dominance and Nash equilibrium in strength. 4.2 Definition We are now ready to give the formal definition. To make the definition a bit simpler, we define its negation when a strategy is not eliminable relative to certain sets of strategies. Definition 2 Given a two-player game in matrix form, subsets D r,e r of the row player s pure strategies Σ r, and subsets D c,e c of the column player s pure strategies Σ c, we say that strategy e r E r is not eliminable relative to D r,e r,d c,e c,if there exist functions (partial mixed strategies) p r : E r [0, 1] and p c : E c [0, 1] with p r (e r) > 0, p r (e r ) 1, and p c (e c ) 1, such that e r E r e c E c 7

8 For any e r E r with p r (e r ) > 0, for any mixed strategy d r placing positive probability only on strategies in D r, there is some pure strategy σ c Σ c E c for the column player such that (letting p σ denote the mixed strategy that results from placing the remaining (unused) probability from the partial mixed strategy p on σ) u r (e r,p c σ c ) u r (d r,p c σ c ). (Or, if p c already uses up all the probability, we simply have u r (e r,p c ) u r (d r,p c ) no σ c needs to be chosen.) The same for the column player: for any e c E c with p c (e c ) > 0, for any mixed strategy d c placing positive probability only on strategies in D c, there is some pure strategy σ r Σ r E r for the row player such that u c (p r σ r,e c ) u c (p r σ r,d c ). (Or, if p r already uses up all the probability, u c (p r,e c ) u c (p r,d c ) no σ r needs to be chosen.) In the example from the previous subsection, we may set D r = {σ 2 r}, D c = {σ 2 c }, E r = {σ 3 r,σ 4 r},e c ={σ 3 c,σ 4 c}, and e r = σ 3 r. Then, by the reasoning that we did, it is impossible to set p r and p c so that the condition is satisfied, and hence σ 3 r is eliminable relative to these sets. 4.3 The spectrum of strength In this subsection we show that our concept spans a spectrum of strength all the way from Nash equilibrium (when the sets D r,e r,d c,e c are chosen as large as possible), to strict dominance (when the sets are chosen as small as possible). We first show that the Nash equilibrium concept is weaker than the elimination concept introduced here in the sense that the elimination concept can never eliminate a strategy that is in some Nash equilibrium. So, if a strategy can be eliminated by the elimination concept, it can be eliminated by the Nash equilibrium concept. Theorem 3 If there is some Nash equilibrium that places positive probability on pure strategy σ r, then σ r is not eliminable relative to any D r,e r,d c,e c. Proof: Let σ r be the row player s strategy in the Nash equilibrium, and let σ c be the column player s strategy in the Nash equilibrium. For any D r,e r,d c,e c with σr E r, simply let p r coincide with σ r on E r that is, let p r be the probabilities that the row player places on the strategies in E r in the equilibrium. (Thus, p r (σr ) > 0). Similarly, let p c coincide with σ c on E c. We will prove that the condition for noneliminability is satisfied for the row player; the case of the column player follows by symmetry. For any e r E r with p r (e r ) > 0, for any mixed strategy d r,we have u r (e r,σ c) u r (d r,σ c) 0, by the Nash equilibrium condition. Now, let σ c arg max σ Σc E c (u r (e r,p c σ) u r (d r,p c σ)). Then we must have u r (e r,p c σ c ) u r (d r,p c σ c ) u r (e r,σ c) u r (d r,σ c) 0(because p c σ c and σ c coincide on E c, and for the former, the remainder of the distribution is chosen to maximize this expression). It follows that σr is not eliminable relative to any D r,e r,d c,e c. We next show that by choosing the sets D r,e r,d c,e c as large as possible, we can make the elimination concept coincide with the Nash equilibrium concept. Theorem 4 Let D r = E r =Σ r and D c = E c =Σ c. Then e r is eliminable relative to these sets if and only if there is no Nash equilibrium that places positive probability on e r. 8

9 Proof: The only if direction follows from Theorem 3. For the if direction, suppose e r is not eliminable relative to D r = E r =Σ r and D c = E c =Σ c. The partial distributions p r and p c with p r (e r) > 0 that show that e r is not eliminable must use up all the probability (the probabilities must sum to one), because there are no strategies outside E c =Σ c and E r =Σ r to place any remaining probability on. Hence, we must have, for any strategy e r E r =Σ r with p r (e r ) > 0, that for any mixed strategy d r, u r (e r,p c ) u r (d r,p c )(and the same for the column player). But these are precisely the conditions for p r and p c to constitute a Nash equilibrium. It follows that there is a Nash equilibrium with positive probability on e r. Incidentally, this leads to the following corollary showing that applying our concept can be computationally hard: Corollary 1 Deciding whether a given strategy is eliminable relative to D r = E r = Σ r and D c = E c =Σ c is conp-complete, even in symmetric 2-player games. Proof: By Theorem 4, this is simply the converse of asking whether there exists a Nash equilibrium with positive probability on the strategy. This is known to be NPcomplete [3], even in this restricted setting [1]. We now show that the concept of strict dominance is stronger than the elimination concept introduced here in the sense that the elimination concept can always eliminate a strictly dominated strategy (as long as the dominating strategy is in D r.) Theorem 5 If pure strategy σ r is strictly dominated by some mixed strategy d r, then σ r is eliminable relative to any D r,e r,d c,e c as long as σ r E r, and all the pure strategies that d r places positive probability on are in D r. Proof: To show that σ r is not eliminable relative to these sets, we must have p r (σ r) > 0, and thus we must demonstrate an inequality of the form u r (σ r,p c σ c ) u r (d r,p c σ c )or u r (σ r,p c ) u r (d r,p c )(because d r only places positive probability on strategies in D r ). But this is impossible, because by strict dominance, u r (σ r,σ c )<u r (d r,σ c ) for any mixed strategy σ c. We next show that by choosing the sets E r,e c as small as possible, we can make the elimination concept coincide with the strict dominance concept. Theorem 6 Let E c = {} and E r = {e r }. Then e r is eliminable relative to D r,e r,d c,e c if and only if it is strictly dominated by some mixed strategy placing positive probability only on elements of D r. Proof: The if direction follows from Theorem 5. For the only if direction, suppose that e r is eliminable relative to these sets. That means that there exists a mixed strategy d r placing positive probability only on strategies in D r such that for any σ c, u(e r,σ c )<u(d r,σ c )(because E c = {} and E r = {e r }, this is the only way in which an attempt to prove that e r is not eliminable could fail). But this is exactly the condition for d r to strictly dominate e r. 4.4 Advantages of the new concept In our opinion, the main benefit of the new concept is that, when a strategy cannot be eliminated by dominance (but it can be eliminated by the Nash equilibrium concept), 9

10 the new concept may present a stronger argument than Nash equilibrium for eliminating the strategy, using sets D r,e r,d c,e c smaller than the entire strategy set. To get the strongest possible argument for eliminating a strategy, the sets D r,e r,d c,e c should be chosen as small as possible while still having the strategy be eliminable relative to these sets. Our definition also allows for iterated elimination of strategies. 5 Conclusions While the Nash equilibrium solution concept is studied more and more intensely in our community, the perhaps more elementary concept of iterated dominance has received much less attention. In this paper, we have made two main contributions. First, we proved some basic complexity results about iterated dominance. We showed that determining whether there is some path that eliminates a given strategy is NP-complete with weak dominance. This allowed us to also show that determining whether there is a path that leads to a unique solution is NP-complete. Both of these results hold regardless of whether dominance by mixed strategies is allowed. (The second result was already known for the case of dominance by pure strategies only, in a slightly less restricted setting [4].) As our second contribution, we presented a new definition of elimination of strategies, and showed that it spans a spectrum of solution concepts from strict dominance to Nash equilibrium. We pointed out that checking whether a strategy is eliminable relative to the sets of all strategies is conp-complete under this definition. References [1] Vincent Conitzer and Tuomas Sandholm. Complexity results about Nash equilibria. In Proceedings of the Eighteenth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI), [2] Drew Fudenberg and Jean Tirole. Game Theory. MIT Press, [3] I. Gilboa and E. Zemel. Nash and correlated equilibria: Some complexity considerations. Games and Economic Behavior, [4] Itzhak Gilboa, Ehud Kalai, and Eitan Zemel. The complexity of eliminating dominated strategies. Mathematics of Operation Research, 18: , [5] C. E. Lemke and J. T. Howson. Equilibrium points of bimatrix games. Journal of the Society of Industrial and Applied Mathematics, 12: , [6] Andreu Mas-Colell, Michael Whinston, and Jerry R. Green. Microeconomic Theory. Oxford University Press, [7] John Nash. Equilibrium points in n-person games. Proc. of the National Academy of Sciences, 36:48 49, [8] Christos Papadimitriou. Algorithms, games and the Internet. In STOC, pages , [9] R. Savani and B. von Stengel. Long Lemke-Howson paths. Technical Report LSE-CDAM , London School of Economics,

Complexity of (Iterated) Dominance

Complexity of (Iterated) Dominance Complexity of (Iterated) Dominance Vincent Conitzer Carnegie Mellon University 5000 Forbes Avenue Pittsburgh, PA 15213, USA conitzer@cs.cmu.edu Tuomas Sandholm Carnegie Mellon University 5000 Forbes Avenue

More information

Finding Equilibria in Games of No Chance

Finding Equilibria in Games of No Chance Finding Equilibria in Games of No Chance Kristoffer Arnsfelt Hansen, Peter Bro Miltersen, and Troels Bjerre Sørensen Department of Computer Science, University of Aarhus, Denmark {arnsfelt,bromille,trold}@daimi.au.dk

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games

ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games University of Illinois Fall 2018 ECE 586GT: Problem Set 1: Problems and Solutions Analysis of static games Due: Tuesday, Sept. 11, at beginning of class Reading: Course notes, Sections 1.1-1.4 1. [A random

More information

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015

Best-Reply Sets. Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis. This version: May 2015 Best-Reply Sets Jonathan Weinstein Washington University in St. Louis This version: May 2015 Introduction The best-reply correspondence of a game the mapping from beliefs over one s opponents actions to

More information

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1

Game theory and applications: Lecture 1 Game theory and applications: Lecture 1 Adam Szeidl September 20, 2018 Outline for today 1 Some applications of game theory 2 Games in strategic form 3 Dominance 4 Nash equilibrium 1 / 8 1. Some applications

More information

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium Chapter 11 Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium In the previous chapter we examined simultaneous move games in which each player had a dominant strategy; the Prisoner s Dilemma game was one example.

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

Rationalizable Strategies

Rationalizable Strategies Rationalizable Strategies Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu Jun 1st, 2015 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics) Game Theory On the Agenda 1

More information

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory

Strategies and Nash Equilibrium. A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory Strategies and Nash Equilibrium A Whirlwind Tour of Game Theory (Mostly from Fudenberg & Tirole) Players choose actions, receive rewards based on their own actions and those of the other players. Example,

More information

January 26,

January 26, January 26, 2015 Exercise 9 7.c.1, 7.d.1, 7.d.2, 8.b.1, 8.b.2, 8.b.3, 8.b.4,8.b.5, 8.d.1, 8.d.2 Example 10 There are two divisions of a firm (1 and 2) that would benefit from a research project conducted

More information

Equilibrium payoffs in finite games

Equilibrium payoffs in finite games Equilibrium payoffs in finite games Ehud Lehrer, Eilon Solan, Yannick Viossat To cite this version: Ehud Lehrer, Eilon Solan, Yannick Viossat. Equilibrium payoffs in finite games. Journal of Mathematical

More information

Game Theory: Normal Form Games

Game Theory: Normal Form Games Game Theory: Normal Form Games Michael Levet June 23, 2016 1 Introduction Game Theory is a mathematical field that studies how rational agents make decisions in both competitive and cooperative situations.

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

Follower Payoffs in Symmetric Duopoly Games

Follower Payoffs in Symmetric Duopoly Games Follower Payoffs in Symmetric Duopoly Games Bernhard von Stengel Department of Mathematics, London School of Economics Houghton St, London WCA AE, United Kingdom email: stengel@maths.lse.ac.uk September,

More information

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies

10.1 Elimination of strictly dominated strategies Chapter 10 Elimination by Mixed Strategies The notions of dominance apply in particular to mixed extensions of finite strategic games. But we can also consider dominance of a pure strategy by a mixed strategy.

More information

Yao s Minimax Principle

Yao s Minimax Principle Complexity of algorithms The complexity of an algorithm is usually measured with respect to the size of the input, where size may for example refer to the length of a binary word describing the input,

More information

An introduction on game theory for wireless networking [1]

An introduction on game theory for wireless networking [1] An introduction on game theory for wireless networking [1] Ning Zhang 14 May, 2012 [1] Game Theory in Wireless Networks: A Tutorial 1 Roadmap 1 Introduction 2 Static games 3 Extensive-form games 4 Summary

More information

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem

Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria, reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem Chapter 10: Mixed strategies Nash equilibria reaction curves and the equality of payoffs theorem Nash equilibrium: The concept of Nash equilibrium can be extended in a natural manner to the mixed strategies

More information

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions and Nash Paths

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions and Nash Paths City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Computer Science Technical Reports Graduate Center 2009 TR-2009015: Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions and Nash Paths Sergei Artemov Follow this and

More information

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming

Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming Introduction to Multi-Agent Programming 10. Game Theory Strategic Reasoning and Acting Alexander Kleiner and Bernhard Nebel Strategic Game A strategic game G consists of a finite set N (the set of players)

More information

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games Tim Roughgarden November 6, 013 1 Canonical POA Proofs In Lecture 1 we proved that the price of anarchy (POA)

More information

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE Answers to Problem Set 2 [1] (a) This is standard (we have even done it in class). The one-shot Cournot outputs can be computed to be A/3, while the payoff to each firm can

More information

Can we have no Nash Equilibria? Can you have more than one Nash Equilibrium? CS 430: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory II (Nash Equilibria)

Can we have no Nash Equilibria? Can you have more than one Nash Equilibrium? CS 430: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory II (Nash Equilibria) CS 0: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory II (Nash Equilibria) ACME, a video game hardware manufacturer, has to decide whether its next game machine will use DVDs or CDs Best, a video game software producer,

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia.

Game theory for. Leonardo Badia. Game theory for information engineering Leonardo Badia leonardo.badia@gmail.com Zero-sum games A special class of games, easier to solve Zero-sum We speak of zero-sum game if u i (s) = -u -i (s). player

More information

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010

Outline Introduction Game Representations Reductions Solution Concepts. Game Theory. Enrico Franchi. May 19, 2010 May 19, 2010 1 Introduction Scope of Agent preferences Utility Functions 2 Game Representations Example: Game-1 Extended Form Strategic Form Equivalences 3 Reductions Best Response Domination 4 Solution

More information

Solution to Tutorial 1

Solution to Tutorial 1 Solution to Tutorial 1 011/01 Semester I MA464 Game Theory Tutor: Xiang Sun August 4, 011 1 Review Static means one-shot, or simultaneous-move; Complete information means that the payoff functions are

More information

6.896 Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory February 10, Lecture 3

6.896 Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory February 10, Lecture 3 6.896 Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory February 0, 200 Lecture 3 Lecturer: Constantinos Daskalakis Scribe: Pablo Azar, Anthony Kim In the previous lecture we saw that there always exists a Nash equilibrium

More information

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory Solution to Tutorial 1 01/013 Semester I MA464 Game Theory Tutor: Xiang Sun August 30, 01 1 Review Static means one-shot, or simultaneous-move; Complete information means that the payoff functions are

More information

Chapter 2 Strategic Dominance

Chapter 2 Strategic Dominance Chapter 2 Strategic Dominance 2.1 Prisoner s Dilemma Let us start with perhaps the most famous example in Game Theory, the Prisoner s Dilemma. 1 This is a two-player normal-form (simultaneous move) game.

More information

Preliminary Notions in Game Theory

Preliminary Notions in Game Theory Chapter 7 Preliminary Notions in Game Theory I assume that you recall the basic solution concepts, namely Nash Equilibrium, Bayesian Nash Equilibrium, Subgame-Perfect Equilibrium, and Perfect Bayesian

More information

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data

Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data Essays on Some Combinatorial Optimization Problems with Interval Data a thesis submitted to the department of industrial engineering and the institute of engineering and sciences of bilkent university

More information

CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory)

CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory) 0 5 CS 798: Homework Assignment 4 (Game Theory) 1.0 Preferences Assigned: October 28, 2009 Suppose that you equally like a banana and a lottery that gives you an apple 30% of the time and a carrot 70%

More information

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S. In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) - Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 8: Simultaneous-Move Games

More information

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization

February 23, An Application in Industrial Organization An Application in Industrial Organization February 23, 2015 One form of collusive behavior among firms is to restrict output in order to keep the price of the product high. This is a goal of the OPEC oil

More information

Log-linear Dynamics and Local Potential

Log-linear Dynamics and Local Potential Log-linear Dynamics and Local Potential Daijiro Okada and Olivier Tercieux [This version: November 28, 2008] Abstract We show that local potential maximizer ([15]) with constant weights is stochastically

More information

TTIC An Introduction to the Theory of Machine Learning. Learning and Game Theory. Avrim Blum 5/7/18, 5/9/18

TTIC An Introduction to the Theory of Machine Learning. Learning and Game Theory. Avrim Blum 5/7/18, 5/9/18 TTIC 31250 An Introduction to the Theory of Machine Learning Learning and Game Theory Avrim Blum 5/7/18, 5/9/18 Zero-sum games, Minimax Optimality & Minimax Thm; Connection to Boosting & Regret Minimization

More information

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma

CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I. Prisoner s Dilemma CS 331: Artificial Intelligence Game Theory I 1 Prisoner s Dilemma You and your partner have both been caught red handed near the scene of a burglary. Both of you have been brought to the police station,

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions? March 3, 215 Steven A. Matthews, A Technical Primer on Auction Theory I: Independent Private Values, Northwestern University CMSEMS Discussion Paper No. 196, May, 1995. This paper is posted on the course

More information

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms

On Existence of Equilibria. Bayesian Allocation-Mechanisms On Existence of Equilibria in Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms Northwestern University April 23, 2014 Bayesian Allocation Mechanisms In allocation mechanisms, agents choose messages. The messages determine

More information

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Graduate School of Management and Economics In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics (for MBA students) 44111 (1393-94 1 st term) - Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Game Theory Game:

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory 3a. More on Normal-Form Games Dana Nau University of Maryland Nau: Game Theory 1 More Solution Concepts Last time, we talked about several solution concepts Pareto optimality

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 14, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria Mixed Strategies

More information

(a) Describe the game in plain english and find its equivalent strategic form.

(a) Describe the game in plain english and find its equivalent strategic form. Risk and Decision Making (Part II - Game Theory) Mock Exam MIT/Portugal pages Professor João Soares 2007/08 1 Consider the game defined by the Kuhn tree of Figure 1 (a) Describe the game in plain english

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design

CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design CS711: Introduction to Game Theory and Mechanism Design Teacher: Swaprava Nath Domination, Elimination of Dominated Strategies, Nash Equilibrium Domination Normal form game N, (S i ) i N, (u i ) i N Definition

More information

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions

TR : Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Computer Science Technical Reports Graduate Center 2009 TR-2009011: Knowledge-Based Rational Decisions Sergei Artemov Follow this and additional works

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 5 [1] Consider an infinitely repeated game with a finite number of actions for each player and a common discount factor δ. Prove that if δ is close enough to zero then

More information

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring Mihai Manea MIT Repeated Games normal-form stage game G = (N, A, u) players simultaneously play game G at time t = 0, 1,... at each date t, players observe all past

More information

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22)

ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson Fall 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) ECON 803: MICROECONOMIC THEORY II Arthur J. Robson all 2016 Assignment 9 (due in class on November 22) 1. Critique of subgame perfection. 1 Consider the following three-player sequential game. In the first

More information

Mixed Strategies. Samuel Alizon and Daniel Cownden February 4, 2009

Mixed Strategies. Samuel Alizon and Daniel Cownden February 4, 2009 Mixed Strategies Samuel Alizon and Daniel Cownden February 4, 009 1 What are Mixed Strategies In the previous sections we have looked at games where players face uncertainty, and concluded that they choose

More information

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves

ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves University of Illinois Spring 01 ECE 586BH: Problem Set 5: Problems and Solutions Multistage games, including repeated games, with observed moves Due: Reading: Thursday, April 11 at beginning of class

More information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Problem Set 1 These questions will go over basic game-theoretic concepts and some applications. homework is due during class on week 4. This [1] In this problem (see Fudenberg-Tirole

More information

Lecture 5: Iterative Combinatorial Auctions

Lecture 5: Iterative Combinatorial Auctions COMS 6998-3: Algorithmic Game Theory October 6, 2008 Lecture 5: Iterative Combinatorial Auctions Lecturer: Sébastien Lahaie Scribe: Sébastien Lahaie In this lecture we examine a procedure that generalizes

More information

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński

Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment. Andrzej Paliński Decision Making in Manufacturing and Services Vol. 9 2015 No. 1 pp. 79 88 Game-Theoretic Approach to Bank Loan Repayment Andrzej Paliński Abstract. This paper presents a model of bank-loan repayment as

More information

Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding October 24, Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding

Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding October 24, Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding Multiunit Auctions: Package Bidding 1 Examples of Multiunit Auctions Spectrum Licenses Bus Routes in London IBM procurements Treasury Bills Note: Heterogenous vs Homogenous Goods 2 Challenges in Multiunit

More information

MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW

MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW MATH 121 GAME THEORY REVIEW ERIN PEARSE Contents 1. Definitions 2 1.1. Non-cooperative Games 2 1.2. Cooperative 2-person Games 4 1.3. Cooperative n-person Games (in coalitional form) 6 2. Theorems and

More information

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers

So we turn now to many-to-one matching with money, which is generally seen as a model of firms hiring workers Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 20 November 13 2008 So far, we ve considered matching markets in settings where there is no money you can t necessarily pay someone to marry

More information

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we

Mixed Strategies. In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we 6 Mixed Strategies In the previous chapters we restricted players to using pure strategies and we postponed discussing the option that a player may choose to randomize between several of his pure strategies.

More information

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership

On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership On Forchheimer s Model of Dominant Firm Price Leadership Attila Tasnádi Department of Mathematics, Budapest University of Economic Sciences and Public Administration, H-1093 Budapest, Fővám tér 8, Hungary

More information

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6 Non-Zero Sum Games R&N Section 17.6 Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games m 11 m 12 m 21 m 22 m ij = Player A s payoff if Player A follows pure strategy i and Player B follows pure strategy j 1 Results so far

More information

CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design

CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design CS711 Game Theory and Mechanism Design Problem Set 1 August 13, 2018 Que 1. [Easy] William and Henry are participants in a televised game show, seated in separate booths with no possibility of communicating

More information

Games and Economic Behavior

Games and Economic Behavior Games and Economic Behavior 69 (2010 512 516 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Games and Economic Behavior www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Note Follower payoffs in symmetric duopoly games Bernhard

More information

Outline for today. Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games. General-sum games. General-sum games. Dominated pure strategies

Outline for today. Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games. General-sum games. General-sum games. Dominated pure strategies Outline for today Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 13: General-Sum Games Peter Bartlett October 11, 2016 Two-player general-sum games Definitions: payoff matrices, dominant strategies, safety strategies, Nash

More information

Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ

Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ Finding Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games Page 1 Finding Mixed-strategy Nash Equilibria in 2 2 Games ÙÛ Introduction 1 The canonical game 1 Best-response correspondences 2 A s payoff as a function

More information

BOUNDS FOR BEST RESPONSE FUNCTIONS IN BINARY GAMES 1

BOUNDS FOR BEST RESPONSE FUNCTIONS IN BINARY GAMES 1 BOUNDS FOR BEST RESPONSE FUNCTIONS IN BINARY GAMES 1 BRENDAN KLINE AND ELIE TAMER NORTHWESTERN UNIVERSITY Abstract. This paper studies the identification of best response functions in binary games without

More information

Solutions of Bimatrix Coalitional Games

Solutions of Bimatrix Coalitional Games Applied Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 8, 2014, no. 169, 8435-8441 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/10.12988/ams.2014.410880 Solutions of Bimatrix Coalitional Games Xeniya Grigorieva St.Petersburg

More information

The efficiency of fair division

The efficiency of fair division The efficiency of fair division Ioannis Caragiannis, Christos Kaklamanis, Panagiotis Kanellopoulos, and Maria Kyropoulou Research Academic Computer Technology Institute and Department of Computer Engineering

More information

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory Part 1: Examples of games We introduce here the basic objects involved in game theory. To specify a game ones gives The players. The set of all possible strategies

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 01 Chapter 5: Pure Strategy Nash Equilibrium Note: This is a only

More information

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i.

Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts. Game in strategic form has following elements. Player set N. (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i. Basic Game-Theoretic Concepts Game in strategic form has following elements Player set N (Pure) strategy set for player i, S i. Payoff function f i for player i f i : S R, where S is product of S i s.

More information

Infinitely Repeated Games

Infinitely Repeated Games February 10 Infinitely Repeated Games Recall the following theorem Theorem 72 If a game has a unique Nash equilibrium, then its finite repetition has a unique SPNE. Our intuition, however, is that long-term

More information

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0

S 2,2-1, x c C x r, 1 0,0 Problem Set 5 1. There are two players facing each other in the following random prisoners dilemma: S C S, -1, x c C x r, 1 0,0 With probability p, x c = y, and with probability 1 p, x c = 0. With probability

More information

The Cascade Auction A Mechanism For Deterring Collusion In Auctions

The Cascade Auction A Mechanism For Deterring Collusion In Auctions The Cascade Auction A Mechanism For Deterring Collusion In Auctions Uriel Feige Weizmann Institute Gil Kalai Hebrew University and Microsoft Research Moshe Tennenholtz Technion and Microsoft Research Abstract

More information

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1

Problem 3 Solutions. l 3 r, 1 . Economic Applications of Game Theory Fall 00 TA: Youngjin Hwang Problem 3 Solutions. (a) There are three subgames: [A] the subgame starting from Player s decision node after Player s choice of P; [B]

More information

Rational Secret Sharing & Game Theory

Rational Secret Sharing & Game Theory Rational Secret Sharing & Game Theory Diptarka Chakraborty (11211062) Abstract Consider m out of n secret sharing protocol among n players where each player is rational. In 2004, J.Halpern and V.Teague

More information

Provocation and the Strategy of Terrorist and Guerilla Attacks: Online Theory Appendix

Provocation and the Strategy of Terrorist and Guerilla Attacks: Online Theory Appendix Provocation and the Strategy of Terrorist and Guerilla s: Online Theory Appendix Overview of Appendix The appendix to the theory section of Provocation and the Strategy of Terrorist and Guerilla s includes

More information

Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems

Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems Comparative Study between Linear and Graphical Methods in Solving Optimization Problems Mona M Abd El-Kareem Abstract The main target of this paper is to establish a comparative study between the performance

More information

COS 511: Theoretical Machine Learning. Lecturer: Rob Schapire Lecture #24 Scribe: Jordan Ash May 1, 2014

COS 511: Theoretical Machine Learning. Lecturer: Rob Schapire Lecture #24 Scribe: Jordan Ash May 1, 2014 COS 5: heoretical Machine Learning Lecturer: Rob Schapire Lecture #24 Scribe: Jordan Ash May, 204 Review of Game heory: Let M be a matrix with all elements in [0, ]. Mindy (called the row player) chooses

More information

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory 16. Behavioral vs. Mixed Strategies Mohammad T. Hajiaghayi University of Maryland Behavioral Strategies In imperfect-information extensive-form games, we can define

More information

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014 HARVARD UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014 You have FOUR hours. Answer all questions Those taking the FINAL have THREE hours Part A (Glaeser): 55

More information

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration

Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Alternating-Offer Games with Final-Offer Arbitration Kang Rong School of Economics, Shanghai University of Finance and Economic (SHUFE) August, 202 Abstract I analyze an alternating-offer model that integrates

More information

Using the Maximin Principle

Using the Maximin Principle Using the Maximin Principle Under the maximin principle, it is easy to see that Rose should choose a, making her worst-case payoff 0. Colin s similar rationality as a player induces him to play (under

More information

CSI 445/660 Part 9 (Introduction to Game Theory)

CSI 445/660 Part 9 (Introduction to Game Theory) CSI 445/660 Part 9 (Introduction to Game Theory) Ref: Chapters 6 and 8 of [EK] text. 9 1 / 76 Game Theory Pioneers John von Neumann (1903 1957) Ph.D. (Mathematics), Budapest, 1925 Contributed to many fields

More information

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #3: Myerson s Lemma

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #3: Myerson s Lemma CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #3: Myerson s Lemma Tim Roughgarden September 3, 23 The Story So Far Last time, we introduced the Vickrey auction and proved that it enjoys three desirable and different

More information

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference.

GAME THEORY. Department of Economics, MIT, Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. 14.126 GAME THEORY MIHAI MANEA Department of Economics, MIT, 1. Existence and Continuity of Nash Equilibria Follow Muhamet s slides. We need the following result for future reference. Theorem 1. Suppose

More information

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Reputations arise in situations where there is an element of repetition, and also where coordination between players is possible. One definition of leadership is that

More information

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions.

Web Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B eb Appendix: Proofs and extensions. B.1 Proofs of results about block correlated markets. This subsection provides proofs for Propositions A1, A2, A3 and A4, and the proof of Lemma A1. Proof of Proposition

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH http://www.kier.kyoto-u.ac.jp/index.html Discussion Paper No. 657 The Buy Price in Auctions with Discrete Type Distributions Yusuke Inami

More information

Regret Minimization and Correlated Equilibria

Regret Minimization and Correlated Equilibria Algorithmic Game heory Summer 2017, Week 4 EH Zürich Overview Regret Minimization and Correlated Equilibria Paolo Penna We have seen different type of equilibria and also considered the corresponding price

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren October, 2013 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games

Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction in Infinite Multiplayer Games Michael Ummels ummels@logic.rwth-aachen.de FSTTCS 2006 Michael Ummels Rational Behaviour and Strategy Construction 1 / 15 Infinite

More information

Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros

Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros Math 167: Mathematical Game Theory Instructor: Alpár R. Mészáros Midterm #1, February 3, 2017 Name (use a pen): Student ID (use a pen): Signature (use a pen): Rules: Duration of the exam: 50 minutes. By

More information

Microeconomic Theory III Final Exam March 18, 2010 (80 Minutes)

Microeconomic Theory III Final Exam March 18, 2010 (80 Minutes) 4. Microeconomic Theory III Final Exam March 8, (8 Minutes). ( points) This question assesses your understanding of expected utility theory. (a) In the following pair of games, check whether the players

More information

Econometrica Supplementary Material

Econometrica Supplementary Material Econometrica Supplementary Material PUBLIC VS. PRIVATE OFFERS: THE TWO-TYPE CASE TO SUPPLEMENT PUBLIC VS. PRIVATE OFFERS IN THE MARKET FOR LEMONS (Econometrica, Vol. 77, No. 1, January 2009, 29 69) BY

More information

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing

Lecture 8: Introduction to asset pricing THE UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON Paul Klein Office: Murray Building, 3005 Email: p.klein@soton.ac.uk URL: http://paulklein.se Economics 3010 Topics in Macroeconomics 3 Autumn 2010 Lecture 8: Introduction

More information

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core

Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core Competitive Outcomes, Endogenous Firm Formation and the Aspiration Core Camelia Bejan and Juan Camilo Gómez September 2011 Abstract The paper shows that the aspiration core of any TU-game coincides with

More information