A Theory of Firm Scope. Oliver Hart (Harvard University and NBER) and. Bengt Holmstrom (MIT and NBER) November 4, 2002*

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A Theory of Firm Scope. Oliver Hart (Harvard University and NBER) and. Bengt Holmstrom (MIT and NBER) November 4, 2002*"

Transcription

1 Firm Scope v 32-2.wpd A Theory of Firm Scope by Oliver Hart (Harvard University and NBER) and Bengt Holmstrom (MIT and NBER) November 4, 2002* *An earlier version of this paper circulated as Vision and Firm Scope. The material presented here formed part of the first author s Munich Lectures (University of Munich, November 2001) and Arrow Lectures (Stanford University, May 2002). We are especially grateful to Andrei Shleifer for insightful comments. We would also like to thank Philippe Aghion, George Baker, Lucian Bebchuk, Pablo Casas-Arce, Mathias Dewatripont, Robert Gibbons, Meg Meyer, Chris Snyder, Jeremy Stein, Lars Stole, Eric van den Steen and seminar audiences at CESifo, University of Munich, Harvard University, London School of Economics, George Washington University, Stanford University, the Summer 2002 Economic Theory Workshop at Gerzensee, Switzerland and the University of Zurich for helpful discussions. Research support from the National Science Foundation is gratefully acknowledged.

2 Abstract The existing literature on firms, based on incomplete contracts and property rights, emphasizes that the ownership of assets--and thereby firm boundaries-- is determined in such a way as to encourage relationship-specific investments by the appropriate parties. It is generally accepted that this approach applies to owner-managed firms better than large companies. In this paper we attempt to broaden the scope of the property rights approach by developing a simpler model with three key ingredients: (a) decisions are non-contractible, but transferable through ownership, (b) managers (and possibly workers) enjoy private benefits that are non-transferable, and (c) owners can divert a firm s profit. With these assumptions firm boundaries matter. Nonintegrated firms fail to account for the external effects that their decisions have on other firms. An integrated firm can internalize such externalities, but it does not put enough weight on the private benefits of managers and workers. We explore this trade-off first in a basic model that focuses on the difficulties companies face in cooperating through the market if benefits are unevenly distributed; therefore they may sometimes end up merging. We then extend the analysis to study industrial structure in a model with intermediate production. This analysis sheds light on industry consolidation in times of excess capacity.

3 1 1. Introduction In the last fifteen years or so, a theoretical literature has developed that argues that the boundaries of firms--and allocation of asset ownership--can be understood in terms of incomplete contracts and property rights. 1 The basic idea behind the literature is that firm boundaries define the allocation of residual control rights and, in a world of incomplete contracts, these matter. In the standard property rights model, parties write contracts that are ex ante incomplete, but that can be completed ex post; the ability to exercise residual control rights improves the ex post bargaining position of an asset owner and thereby increases her incentive, and the incentive of those who enjoy significant gains from trade with her, to make relationship-specific investments; and as a consequence it is optimal to assign asset ownership to those who have the most important relationship-specific investments, or who have indispensable human capital. 2 Although the property rights approach provides a clear explanation of the costs and benefits of integration, as a number of people have argued, the theory seems to describe ownermanaged firms better than large companies. 3 There are several ways to see this. First, according to the theory, the major impact of a change in ownership is on those who gain or lose ownership rights; however, in a merger between two large companies it is often the case that the key decision-makers (the CEOs, for example) do not have substantial ownership rights before or after the merger. Second, the relationship-specific investments analyzed are made by individuals rather than by firms; this again resonates more with the case of small firms than large companies. 1 See Grossman and Hart (1986), Hart and Moore (1990), and Hart (1995). This literature builds on the earlier transaction cost literature of Williamson (1975, 1985) and Klein, Crawford and Alchian (1978). 2 Extensions of the model show that it is sometimes optimal to take assets away from someone to improve their incentives to make relationship-specific investments (e.g., to discourage rent-seeking behavior). On this, see Baker, Gibbons and Murphy (2002a), Chiu (1998), de Meza and Lockwood (1998), and Rajan and Zingales (1998). For some recent empirical work supporting the property rights approach, see Baker and Hubbard (2002), Elfenbein and Lerner (2002) and Woodruff (2002). 3 For a discussion of this and related points, see Holmstrom and Roberts (1998) and Holmstrom (1999).

4 2 Third, and perhaps most important, the approach envisions a situation of autarchy, in which all the relevant parties meet and bargain ex post over the gains from trade, and the only issue is who has the right to walk away with which assets; there are no other decisions in the model. As it stands the model has no room for organizational structure, hierarchy or delegation ; in an important sense, the model continues to describe a pure market economy, although one enriched by the idea that individuals can be empowered through the ownership of key nonhuman assets. The purpose of the current paper is to modify the property rights approach so that it can be applied to a broader set of organizational issues, including industrial organization and the organization of large firms. We begin by describing the key ingredients of our general approach. Firms are characterized by the scope of their activities. We suppose that the economy has a given set of activities and we ask how these activities should be grouped to form firms. To be concrete, we will associate each activity with a production unit. We may think of a unit as an irreducible set of activities that it would be meaningless to break up further. Each unit has a manager and possibly also some workers. The owner of the unit is the boss. The unit manager could be the boss or the unit could be owned by an outside boss (sometimes referred to as a professional manager). The identity of the boss will be important. The decisions in each unit are noncontractible (ex ante and ex post). Units can be bought and sold. Ownership of a unit confers the right to make the decisions in that unit. The fact that decisions can be transferred only through ownership, and are not even ex post contractible, is a central feature of our model and distinguishes it from the standard property rights model in which decisions are ex ante noncontractible but ex post contractible. Many decisions are of course contractible; for instance those involving trade between two firms. But there are probably many more decisions that firms make unilaterally, such as setting prices, choosing production techniques, deciding on marketing campaigns, assigning workers, determining incentive schemes, and so on. Some of these decisions have to be made unilaterally (e.g. pricing decisions); others are made unilaterally, because no one else has an interest in them. Our focus is on decisions that have potential external effects (positive or negative), yet are impossible to agree upon contractually. In these cases, changes in ownership are the only way to affect how decisions are made and how well they take into account external effects.

5 3 Full integration would always be optimal if all the benefits and costs from decisions were transferrable through ownership. To avoid this uninteresting conclusion, we assume that each unit generates two kinds of benefit: monetary profit and private (nontransferable) benefits in the form of job satisfaction for those working in the unit. For the most part we will assume that the manager is the only worker and hence private benefits refer to her job satisfaction. (We will return to discuss the source of private benefits in more detail later.) We assume that the boss of a unit can divert all the profit from that unit to herself. This simplifies the analysis by ruling out profit sharing as a way to influence incentives. To illustrate how firm boundaries affect decision making, consider the simplest setting with two units A and B. Denote the pair of profits and private benefits (measured in money) accruing to each by (v A, w A ) and (v B, w B ), respectively. Then if the units are nonintegrated, and manager A is the boss of unit A, and manager B the boss of unit B, manager A will maximize v A + w A since she diverts the profit from unit A and cares about her own private benefits; and manager B will maximize v B + w B for similar reasons. In contrast, if units A and B are integrated, then what happens depends on who is the overall boss. If manager A is the overall boss, manager A will maximize v A + v B + w A, since she diverts the profit from both units, and cares about her own private benefit but not manager B s. Similarly, if manager B is the overall boss, she will maximize v A + v B + w B. Finally, if a (professional) outsider is brought in to be the boss, she will maximize v A + v B, since she diverts all the profit and does not care about private benefits. As a reference point, note that social optimality is achieved by maximizing total surplus: v A + v B + w A + w B. The important point here is that integration results in less weight being placed on private benefits than nonintegration. Under nonintegration w A, w B each appear in one boss s objective function. In contrast, under integration, at least one of the w s fails to appear in the overall objective function. However, this diminished influence of private benefits is offset by the fact that under integration total profits rather than individual unit profits are maximized. In summary, under nonintegration, bosses maximize the right thing (profits plus private benefits) but are parochial (they do not take into account their effect on the other unit), while

6 4 under integration they maximize the wrong thing but are broad. We analyze two models of firm boundaries based on the general trade-off described above. The first, discussed in Section 2, is concerned with interactions between two units. To simplify matters, we suppose that each unit has a binary decision to make: it can either act in an accommodating way vis-a-vis the other unit or not. For example, the unit could accommodate by deciding not to poach on the other unit s territory or by being less aggressive in its advertising; or the unit could choose a technology or a standard that is beneficial to the other unit; or it could provide the other unit with some key piece of knowledge. Each of these examples has the characteristic that it may be too costly or impossible to agree on a decision contractually. Only by owning the unit can one control the decision. We ask whether units A and B will be regulated better if the units remain independent or if they integrate. Call the case where both parties accommodate coordination. We show that, under reasonable assumptions, nonintegration leads to too little coordination; for some parameter values for which coordination is optimal, coordination will not be a Nash Equilibrium if units stay separate. There are two reasons why this may happen. The first is the well known prisoner s dilemma problem: both units may be better off with coordination, but unilaterally each prefers to deviate. The other reason is that while coordination may be socially optimal (total surplus maximizing), the distribution of gains may be so uneven that one of the parties will not want to go along (accommodate). In contrast, under a weak assumption--specifically, that coordination represents a reduction in independence and therefore causes a fall in private benefits--integration leads to too much coordination. The reason is that an outsider boss may choose to coordinate even though it destroys significant private benefits, because it is more profitable. In the model described above there is no role for outsourcing: decisions are always made inside the units and the only question is whether they are made by one boss or two. In reality, outsourcing of a decision or activity is often a viable alternative for an organization. For example, consider two units in the output market that need a specialized input. Then each unit can remain separate and provide the input in-house; or the units can merge horizontally and collectively provide the input in-house; or the units can remain separate and procure the input from an

7 5 independent supplier. In Section 3 we present a model that analyzes these choices (the model covers similar ground to Bolton and Whinston (1993), but the approach is different). We assume that the two units, or buyers, have stochastic input demands or valuations. The buyers can collectively choose whether to have one or two units of capacity in the upstream market. With two units of capacity, both buyers will be supplied, while with one unit only one buyer will be supplied. Given that valuations are stochastic, it may be efficient to save on capacity and have only one unit. However, saving on capacity typically requires coordination and specialization: the limited capacity must be dedicated or directed to the buyer with the greater needs. There are two leading organizational forms with one unit of capacity. In one the supplier is an independent firm ( outsourcing ); in the other the two buyers and a single seller merge into one firm ( complete integration ). (We also compare these with an organizational form with two units of capacity.) We show that in some cases potential savings in capacity can be exploited only under complete integration. The reason is that under other organizational forms the supplier may be unwilling to specialize to any one buyer. We argue that this model captures the idea of integrating for synergy. Note that in order to allow for outsourcing we have to drop the assumption that ex post trade is noncontractible; instead we suppose that the decision to specialize to a buyer is noncontractible. The interpretation that private benefits are enjoyed by a single manager is restrictive in that it implies that the units are in effect sole proprietorships under nonintegration. It is worth mentioning a second interpretation of the model that applies to the case where the units are large companies. One can interpret the private benefit w i (i = A,B) as representing the aggregate job satisfaction of all the unit i workers rather than the private benefits of a single manager. Suppose that there is a population of bosses with different preferences, some of whom care about the firm s activities in addition to its profits, and others of whom care only about money. Call the first group enthusiasts, and suppose that there is an enthusiast corresponding to each unit: a unit A enthusiast has goals that are (partially) congruent with those of unit A workers, and hence puts some weight on w A ; while a unit B enthusiast has goals that are (partially) congruent with those of

8 6 unit B workers, and hence puts some weight on w B. 4 Assume as before that a boss can divert some fraction of the profit of any unit under her control to herself--but that this fraction is now less than 1. Then, under an appropriate assumption about the degree of congruence between bosses and workers and about the fraction, of profit diverted, a unit i enthusiast will maximize v i + w i under nonintegration. In contrast, under integration, a professional will maximize v A + v B. We will show that this version of the model is analytically identical to the first one. Now the benefit of nonintegration for the owners of units A and B is that, since workers private benefits are respected by an enthusiastic boss, workers will work for lower wages. 5 Our paper is related to a number of ideas that have appeared elsewhere in the literature. First, there is an overlap with the recent literature on internal capital markets; see particularly Stein (1997, 2002), Scharfstein and Stein (2000), Rajan, Servaes and Zingales (2000), Brusco and Panunzi (2000), and Inderst and Laux (2000). This literature emphasizes the idea that the boss of a conglomerate firm, even if she is an empire builder, is interested in the overall profit of the conglomerate, rather than the profits of any particular division. As a result, the conglomerate boss will do a good job of allocating capital to the most profitable project ( winner-picking ). Our idea that the professional boss of an integrated firm maximizes total profit is similar to this; the 4 A boss may be biased toward its workforce because sustained contact with workers fosters friendship and empathy. Wrestling with the same problems, sharing the same information, and having a similar professional background are all conducive to a common vision that aligns interests, particularly on issues such as the strategic direction of the firm. Shleifer and Summers (1988) argue that it may be an efficient long-run strategy for a firm to bring up or train prospective bosses to be committed to workers and other stakeholders (on this, see also Blair and Stout (1999)). Milgrom and Roberts (1988) argue that frequent interaction gives workers the opportunity to articulate their views and influence the minds of their bosses, sometimes to the detriment of the firm. All these explanations are consistent with our assumption that the boss of a firm with broad scope will put less weight on private benefits than a boss of a firm with a narrow scope. The reason is that, with a broader range of activities, the firm s workforce will be more heterogeneous, making the boss experience less empathy for any given group. Also the intensity of contact with any particular group will go down, reducing the ability of that group s workers to influence the boss. 5 There is some evidence consistent with this. Schoar (2001), in a study of the effects of corporate diversification on plant level productivity, finds that diversified firms have on average 7% more productive plants but pay their workers on average 8% more than comparable stand alone firms.

9 7 main differences are that the internal capital markets literature does not stress the same cost of integration as we do--the insufficient emphasis on private benefits--or allow for the possibility that the allocation of capital can be done through the market (in our models, the market is always an alternative to centralized decision-making), or consider general coordination (or accommodation) decisions. Second, the idea that it may be efficient for the firm to have narrow scope and/or choose a boss that is biased toward particular workers is familiar from the work of Shleifer and Summers (1988), Rotemberg and Saloner (1994, 2000), and Van den Steen (2001). These papers emphasize the effect of narrow scope and bias on worker incentives rather than on private benefits or wages, but the underlying premise, that workers care about the boss s preferences, is the same. However, none of these papers analyzes firm boundaries. Third, there are several recent papers that like this one use the idea that some actions are noncontractible ex ante and ex post but may be transferable through owership; see, e.g., Aghion, Dewatripont and Rey (2002), Baker et al. (2002b), Bolton and Dewatripont (2001), Hart and Moore (2000), Holmstrom (1999), and Mailath et al. (2002). Mailath et al. (2002) is probably the paper closest to ours. They analyze a model in which the boss of an integrated firm maximizes total profit and so internalizes externalities. However, the cost of integration in their paper is a decline in worker initiative resulting from hold-up, rather than an insufficient emphasis on private benefits. 2. A basic model of coordination Our first model concerns two units, which might operate in the same or similar output or input markets. Each unit makes decisions that affect the other unit. We will analyze whether the interaction between units will be regulated more efficiently if the units remain independent or if they integrate. 6 Each unit has a binary decision: it can choose Yes or No. We interpret Yes to mean that the unit acts in an accommodating (or compromising) way vis-a-vis the other unit, and No to mean that it does not. To have a concrete example in mind, think of two newspapers. Each one 6 Here efficiency is defined with respect to the owners, managers and workers of the units. We ignore the impact of the units decisions on consumers, e.g., in the form of reduced competition. Of course, in certain contexts, such anti-trust issues may be very important.

10 8 can decide whether to cater to the mass of readers or to specialize. Accommodation by one unit corresponds to the case where it specializes, for instance, by going up market. We focus on the binary case, because it highlights clearly the two main economic reasons for integrating. At the beginning an organizational form is selected--specifically, whether the units should be separate firms (nonintegration, i.e., there are two bosses) or should merge into one firm (integration, i.e., there is one boss), and also what kind of boss should be in charge. Next, each unit decides whether to choose Yes or No. Finally, the payoffs are realized. The time-line is as in Figure 1. Organizational Decision Payoffs form chosen made realized Figure 1 We assume that the decision in each unit is made by the boss of that unit. We also suppose that these decisions are noncontractible, both ex ante and ex post. This implies that contracts in which one unit agrees to choose Yes, say, in return for a side-payment from the other unit cannot be enforced. In other words, Coasian bargaining will not ensure efficiency of the accommodation decisions. We represent the payoffs from different outcomes in the following matrix. We assume that these payoffs are nonverifiable and, for simplicity, perfectly certain.

11 9 Unit B Y N A: v A (Y,Y), w A (Y,Y) A: v A (Y,N), w A (Y,N) Y B: v B (Y,Y), w B (Y,Y) B: v B (Y,N), w B (Y,N) Unit A A: v A (N,Y), w A (N,Y) A: v A (N,N), w A (N,N) N B: v B (N,Y), w B (N,Y) B: v B (N,N), w B (N,N) Figure 2 Here unit A is the row player and unit B is the column player. The entries are the payoffs. The first coordinate v refers to profit and the second coordinate w to private benefits (private benefits are measured in money). Subscripts refer to units, i.e., (v A, w A ) denotes unit A s payoffs and (v B, w B ) unit B s. It will be convenient to introduce the notation (2.1) z A v A + w A, z B v B + w B. Here z A refers to total surplus in unit A, z B to total surplus in unit B, and z A + z B equals aggregate social surplus. As noted in the introduction, private benefits refer (broadly) to job satisfaction, or on-thejob consumption. It is reasonable to suppose that part of job satisfaction stems from the ability to pursue an independent course or agenda. Thus we will assume that coordination (accommodation by both units) leads to a reduction in total private benefits: (2.2) w A (Y,Y) + w B (Y,Y) w A (N,N) + w B (N,N).

12 10 Note that we allow one side, but not both, to benefit privately from coordination. This may be reasonable, for instance, if coordination corresponds to the adoption of a common standard (see later). Also, note that we put no restrictions on whether coordination increases or decreases profits; moreover, even if coordination increases total profits, profits may rise by more or less than the fall in private benefits, i.e., (Y,Y) may be more or less (socially) efficient than (N,N) (z A (Y,Y) + z B (Y,Y) z A (N,N) + z B (N,N)). We mentioned in the introduction several interpretations of private benefits. We begin by focusing on the simplest one: Each unit contains one individual (a manager), who enjoys the private benefits w; in addition, a boss can divert all the profit from the units she operates. Then there are two leading organizational forms: (1) Nonintegration: Manager A is the boss of unit A and manager B is the boss of unit B, i.e., the units are sole proprietorships. Manager A maximizes z A and manager B maximizes z B. (2) Integration: A professional manager (outsider) is the boss of both units and managers A and B are subordinates. The professional manager maximizes v A + v B. Note that, in (1), the managers play a noncooperative game, while in (2) no strategic elements are involved: the professional manager simply maximizes total profit. Note also the critical role played by the assumption that the accommodation/nonaccommodation decisions are noncontractible. In the absence of this, the parties would negotiate to an efficient ex post outcome using sidepayments, i.e., z A + z B would be maximized under all organizational forms. (1) and (2) are not the only possible organizational forms. If the units are under common ownership, manager A (resp., manager B), rather than a professional, could be the boss; she would then maximize v A + v B + w A (resp., v A + v B + w B ). Furthermore, even if the units are separately owned, they could be run by a professional manager (it is even possible that manager A could be the boss of unit B and vice versa). However, in the case of certainty, the first-best can always be achieved by (1) or (2). Thus we focus on these.

13 11 Although the decisions Yes or No are noncontractible ex ante and ex post, we will assume that organizational form is contractible at the beginning of the period. Coasian bargaining will then ensure that organizational form is chosen efficiently, i.e., to maximize total surplus (z A + z B ) (there are no wealth constraints and information is symmetric). To spell this out a little more: if the units are initially manager-owned but integration is more efficient, then a professional manager will purchase control rights from managers A and B at prices such that all three parties are better off (in particular, manager i s private benefit under the professional manager plus the lump sum she receives for her control rights is at least equal to her payoff under nonintegration); and if the units are initially owned by a professional manager, and nonintegration is more efficient, then managers A and B will purchase control rights from the professional manager at prices such that all three parties are better off. In summary, organizational form is chosen at the beginning of period 1 to maximize the value of z A + z B in the subsequent game. We will make the following technical assumption. We will suppose that total surplus and total profit are maximized either if both parties accommodate or if neither does. That is, (2.3) Max [z A (Y,Y) + z B (Y,Y), z A (N,N) + z B (N,N)] Max [z A (Y,N) + z B (Y,N), z A (N,Y) + z B (N,Y)], (2.4) Max [v A (Y,Y) + v B (Y,Y), v A (N,N) + v B (N,N)] Max [v A (Y,N) + v B (Y,N), v A (N,Y) + v B (N,Y)]. We will see that in this model nonintegration can cause two kinds of inefficiency. The first occurs when coordination yields greater social surplus than non-coordination, but one party loses out, i.e., the distribution of payoffs is uneven; this party will then refuse to accommodate. The second inefficiency occurs when both parties benefit from coordination but coordination is not a Nash equilibrium, i.e., at least one party wants to deviate (this is the standard prisoner s dilemma or free rider problem).

14 12 Pure coordination It will be useful to separate out these effects even though in most real world situations they are combined. Thus we begin by analyzing the case where only the first inefficiency is present; we call this pure coordination: (2.5) v A (Y,N) = v A (N,Y) = v A (N,N), v B (Y,N) = v B (N,Y) = v B (N,N), w A (Y,N) = w A (N,Y) = w A (N,N), w B (Y,N) = w B (N,Y) = w B (N,N). Pure coordination refers to a situation where accommodation by one party has no effect at all on payoffs, i.e., it takes two to accommodate. An example would be if each party must decide whether to adopt a standard, and the standard has no force unless both parties adopt. Under pure coordination, the prisoner s dilemma or free rider problem does not arise since nonaccommodation by either party is equivalent to non-accommodation by both. Given (2.5), it is easy to see what the trade-off between nonintegration and integration is. Under nonintegration, each boss in effect has a veto on coordination, since by choosing nonaccommodation she can achieve the (N,N) outcome. Thus (Y,Y) will occur if and only if (Y,Y) Pareto dominates (N,N): (2.6) z A (Y,Y) z A (N,N), z B (Y,Y) z B (N,N). Note that even if (2.6) holds, (N,N) is always a Nash equilibrium along with (Y,Y); however, we will suppose that the parties do not pick a Pareto dominated equilibrium. It is of course immediate that (2.6) implies that (Y,Y) is socially efficient: (2.7) z A (Y,Y) + z B (Y,Y) z A (N,N) + z B (N,N). However, equally clearly, the converse is not true: (2.7) does not imply (2.6). This is the problem of winners and losers, mentioned earlier. Even though aggregate surplus may rise, the distribution may be such that one party loses out, and this party will then veto coordination, leading to the

15 13 outcome (N,N). Let us now turn to integration. Under integration, a single boss chooses the outcome that maximizes total profit. This outcome will be (Y,Y) or (N,N) according to whether (2.8) v A (Y,Y) + v B (Y,Y) v A (N,N) + v B (N,N). It follows from (2.2) that, under integration, (Y,Y) is always the outcome if it is efficient, but may be the outcome even if it is inefficient. Figure 3 illustrates the outcomes under nonintegration and integration. 7 In the figure, v i = v i (Y,Y) - v i (N,N) and w i = w i (Y,Y) - w i (N,N), i = A, B; these are the changes in profits and private benefits that result from a decision by both parties to accommodate. We have drawn the figure keeping w A, w B fixed and letting v A, v B be variable, but this of course is done merely to stay within two dimensions. In general, we are interested in the mapping from profits v and private benefits w into the choice of organizational form. ============ Figure 3 here ============ The first-best decision rule (2.7) is represented by the line FB-FB; all pairs of profit gains ( v A, v B ) that fall above this line call for coordination. In a similar way, line I-I represents the decision rule (2.8) and the quadrant NI-NI the decision rule under non-integration. Note that FB- FB is above I-I, because the sum of the changes in private benefits are assumed negative by (2.2). The figure shows that nonintegration and integration make the opposite kind of mistake. Under nonintegration there is too little coordination in the sense that (Y,Y) never occurs if it is inefficient, but may not occur if it is efficient. Under integration, there is too much coordination in the sense that (Y,Y) is always the outcome if it is efficient, but may be the outcome even if it is inefficient. It follows that nonintegration achieves the first-best if (N,N) is efficient (since nonintegration errs on the side of too little coordination but never too much), while integration 7 We thank George Baker for suggesting this picture.

16 14 achieves the first-best if (Y,Y) is efficient (since integration errs on the side of too much coordination but never too little). It is also clear from Figure 3 that for some parameter values nonintegration and integration both achieve the first-best. This is the case when (Y,Y) is the outcome under nonintegration or when (N,N) is the outcome under integration. In all other cases it is essential to choose the right organizational form. Nonintegration will lead to inefficiency if profit gains from coordination are sufficiently unevenly distributed between the two firms; staying above the FB-FB line and moving in parallel with it will eventually take us outside the NI-NI acceptance region. Integration will lead to inefficiency if private costs from coordination are large enough; raising private costs will move the FB-FB/NI-NI part of the figure to the North-East and eventually make (N,N) the first-best choice. 8 We summarize the discussion in Proposition 1. Assume pure coordination, i.e., (2.5). Then, if (N,N) is efficient, nonintegration (with unit managers as bosses) achieves the first-best. If (Y,Y) is efficient, integration (with a professional manager as boss) achieves the first-best. Furthermore, integration will be uniquely optimal if profit gains from coordination are sufficiently unevenly divided between units. Nonintegration will be uniquely optimal if private costs from coordination are sufficiently high in aggregate. General Coordination The case of pure coordination is, of course, quite restrictive. In many situations, one party s decision to accommodate will affect payoffs, whether or not the other party accommodates. For example, accommodation could refer to a decision by one unit to raise its 8 In Figure 3 the region of inefficient integration could be reduced by letting manager B run the integrated unit. This way B s private benefits would be accounted for, something manager A would be happy with as long as she also dislikes coordination. However, (2.2) admits the case where A enjoys private benefits from coordination (say, because it involves the use of her firm s technology). In that case, (2.2) implies that manager B would coordinate too little relative to first-best and hence the comparison to a professional manager would be ambiguous. We do not explore these options here, since we get first best either way.

17 15 price (or lower its output), or not to poach on the unit s territory. If the other unit produces a substitute good, this will increase the other unit s profit, regardless of whether it raises its price, or decides not to poach too. We show in the Appendix that our analysis generalizes to cases where it does not take two to accomodate, as long as we are prepared to make some assumptions. An alternative interpretation of private benefits So far we have emphasized the interpretation where the private benefits w i are enjoyed by a single manager in each unit, who is the boss under nonintegration and a subordinate under integration. However, as noted in the introduction, there is a second interpretation of the model that is also of interest. We can imagine that the private benefits refer to the job satisfaction of unit i workers and that some bosses have goals that are (partially) congruent with those of the workers, i.e., they care about the same things. In particular, suppose that there are three types of bosses, unit A enthusiasts with preferences m + A w A ; unit B enthusiasts with preferences m + B w B ; and professional managers with preferences m. Here m is money and A, B represent congruence between a boss s goals and those of unit A and B workers. Suppose now that a boss can divert a fraction < 1 of total profit toward herself; one can imagine that she uses this profit for perks or empire-building activities that benefit her alone-- fancy offices, secretaries, pet projects, etc. Denote profit by v. Then a unit i enthusiast will maximize (2.9) v + i w i, while a professional manager will maximize v. 9 If we make the simplifying assumption that = A = B, this yields the same objective 9 With partial diversion, it may be desirable to give manager A a share of the residual profits of unit B in order to get closer to first-best, but we will not pursue this possibility here.

18 16 function for the different kinds of bosses as in the model without workers described above. 10 In this interpretation, the choice of organizational form is made by the initial owner(s) of units A and B at the beginning of the period. They must decide whether the units should be separate (nonintegration) or together (integration), and what kind of boss to put in charge. Assume that owners face a competitive labor market and wages are agreed up front. Then the (total) wage i for unit i workers will satisfy (2.10) i + w i = U, where U is the (total) market clearing reservation wage and w i refers to (expected) worker private benefits. Suppose that the initial owner(s) wish to sell out and retire, i.e., they are interested only in money. Then, given that side-payments are possible, organizational form will be selected to maximize the total value of the two units net of wages, i.e., given (2.10), v A + v B + w A + w B (we ignore the private benefits and remuneration of bosses). We may conclude that the analysis of this second interpretation of the model is identical to the previous one. Discussion We have interpreted the model in this section as being about horizontal interaction, suggesting that it is primarily about interactions between firms in the same market. This is needlessly narrow. Our approach has potential relevance whenever firms have to make decisions unilaterally, because bargaining over those decisions is too costly. Here we want to discuss briefly the broader relevance of the model using two illustrative examples. Knowledge transfers. Knowledge is notoriously difficult to sell. It is often difficult to codify. It is also hard to circumscribe the use of knowledge once it has been transferred to another party. The transfer of knowledge from one firm to another may be very valuable, but it may be 10 It is obviously important that there is no boss who is an enthusiast for both units A and B. Under integration such a boss would maximize (v A + v B ) + A w A + B w B, and, if = A = B, this would yield the first-best.

19 17 very difficult to arrange things so that the benefits of the transfer are appropriately divided between the firms. For this reason, knowledge transfer can be a major impetus for integration. The 1960s saw a wave of mergers and acquisitions, which partly were driven by regulation and partly were guided by new management technology that was best appropriated by buying up firms and implementing the new management systems after that. 11 Note that once the knowledge transfer is complete and the new systems are up and running, one may well expect divestment of some of the units. Subsequent divestments are often read as signs of failed mergers, but if the initial reason for a merger was knowledge transfer, that verdict may be misguided. To study this sequence of events, we could extend our model to two periods. In the first period the key decision is whether to transfer knowledge by merging. In the second period, assuming a merger, divestment may become optimal, because decisions with significant private benefits come to dominate the payoffs. The analysis of such a two-period model is more complicated than piecing together two one-period analyses, because the payoffs from the second stage will determine how much should be paid in the first-period merger. Also, the first-period decision will in general influence the second period payoffs and options. Technology choice. Standards are important in emerging industries like information technology. The social benefits from a common standard can be huge, because it increases the overall market. Yet, getting parties to agree to a standard is very difficult. Most of the time industry agreements have to rely on self-enforcement, which tends to be ineffective. Instead, proprietary systems may become de facto standards. Cisco s operating system is an example of a dominant standard/platform in the Internet space. Should an entrepreneur with a new idea choose to develop it for the Cisco standard or should it try to do something more generic? The entrepreneur needs to be assured that Cisco will not take advantage of his choice later on. If this is difficult contractually, as it often is, the alternative may be integration. This situation again fits our model. Suppose the entrepreneur s total payoff goes down if he unilaterally chooses to choose Cisco s standard, because contractual guarantees are ineffective. Then, if the social value of using Cisco s standard is sufficiently positive, Cisco could buy out the 11 Much of the knowledge transfer is conducted by management consulting firms these days. The outsourcing model in the next section could be used to study that development.

20 18 entrepreneur. The transfer of decision rights would justify the transfer of payments. In the late 1990s Cisco was very active buying start-ups as a way of expanding its technology base. Cisco s reputation for preserving the entrepreneur s private benefits inside the firm made this strategy work particularly well (until the downturn hit). A richer analysis would include an innovation stage as well as a buy-out stage. It seems reasonable to assume that the entrepreneur s private benefits are initially high relative to the benefits of a buy-out. 12 Indeed, one typically does not know whether the entrepreneur will be successful and if so, whether the innovation will fit Cisco s technology rather than some other company. (An important reason why private benefits are so high initially is that the entrepreneur has exaggerated beliefs about the probability of success; see, e.g. Van den Steen, 2001). Thus, it is often best to let innovation take place on a stand-alone basis. Once the project has matured to a stage where valuations are more clearly in view a buy-out may be optimal. It is worth noting that dynamic extensions of the basic model would often lead to analyses that resemble those encountered in traditional models of hold-up. In the Cisco case the entrepreneur may not want to specialize to Cisco s standard, because he fears that Cisco will then by virtue of controlling the technology be able to appropriate much of the later benefits of cooperation. There are important differences, however, between our approach and the traditional way of modeling hold-ups using incomplete contracts. In the traditional model, individuals make noncontractible human capital investments; asset ownership influences the payoffs from these investments, but not who makes the investments. Our focus is not on human capital investments, typically, but on strategic decisions with opportunity costs for the organization; asset ownership determines who makes these decisions. This structure reflects the reality that firms are organizational entities rather than mere entrepreneurs. It is also a potentially simpler way of studying hold-up problems. work hard. 12 It may, of course, also be more important at this stage to motivate the entrepreneur to

21 19 3. An extension to outsourcing. In Section 2 we analyzed a model in which two units may find it easier to coordinate behavior (achieve accommodation) under common ownership than under separate ownership. In that model there was no role for outsourcing: decisions were always made inside the units and the only question was whether they were made by one boss or two. In reality, outsourcing of a decision or activity is often a viable alternative for an organization. For example, consider two units, operating in the same or similar output markets, that need a specialized input. The input could be an intermediate good or it could be a service like advertising or marketing. Each unit can remain separate and provide the service in-house; or the two units can merge horizontally and collectively provide the service in-house; or the units can remain separate and procure the service from an independent supplier. In this section we will develop a model that allows us to analyze the trade-off between these choices (and others too). Among other things the model will throw light on the often-mentioned idea that firms merge horizontally to exploit synergies ; here the synergies will stem from the ability to reduce costs by sharing scarce input capacity. In order to allow for the possibility of outsourcing, we need to permit some contractibility; ie., we have to relax the assumption of Section 2 that everything is ex post noncontractible. Instead we will suppose that the parties can contract on the quantity and quality of input at the time of delivery. However, we will assume that at an earlier stage a decision must be made as to how specialized the input is. This decision is noncontractible (ex ante and ex post) and is made by the boss of the supplying unit. To make the trade-offs interesting, we also need the units profits to be stochastic ex ante; that is, we will depart from the assumption of perfect certainty made in Section 2. The economy lasts for one period. At the beginning of the period, organizational form is chosen. In the middle of the period any uncertainty is resolved and a specialization decision is made. Finally, at the end of the period trade occurs and payoffs are realized. The time-line is as in Figure 4.

22 20 Organizational State learned Trade and form chosen and specialization payoffs decision made realized Figure 4 One buyer. We start with the simplest case of one buyer operating in the output market and one seller operating in the input market--we refer to them as B and S. B requires a specialized input, one widget, say, at the end of the period. S has one unit of capacity, costing k, which can be used to supply one widget at the end of the period. S s variable costs are zero. This widget can be supplied either to B or to the outside market, which is assumed to be competitive. The competitive market price is r. S must make a choice in the middle of the period. To supply B at the end of the period, S must specialize to B; but then S can t supply the outside market. Alternatively, S can choose to remain flexible and supply the outside market; but then S cannot supply B. The value to B of a (specialized) widget is v. In addition B s manager receives a private benefit w if the widget is supplied. (We ignore any private benefits of S s manager or managers in the outside market; we assume they are independent of transactions with B.) The variables v, w, r are uncertain at the beginning of the period. However, the uncertainty is resolved before the specialization decision is made; moreover, v, w, r are observable to B and S (but are not verifiable). We assume that no long-term contracts can be written about the end-of-period widget price (because widget characteristics cannot be specified in advance) although spot contracts at the end of the period are possible. As in Section 2, we suppose that the boss of a unit diverts all the profit from that unit. We also suppose that all parties are risk neutral. In this model, the key decision is whether to specialize. This decision is made by whoever is the boss of S. We focus on two organizational forms: (1) B and S are independent firms and each is run by its manager (nonintegration).

23 21 (2) B and S are a single firm run by B s manager (vertical integration). As in Section 2, these are not the only possibilities. For example, B and S could be separate and B could be run by a professional manager. Or B and S could be one firm run by S s manager. But (1) and (2) are leading cases. Assume first that B and S are nonintegrated. Suppose S specializes to B. Then at the end of the period S and B will bargain about the price of the input. Assume that they divide the gains from trade 50 : 50. Since B s boss values the widget at v + w and S s (variable) costs are zero, this means that S will receive ½ (v + w). In contrast, if S does not specialize and sells on the open market, S will receive r. It follows that S will specialize to B if and only if (3.1) ½ (v + w) > r. (Recall that S knows v, w, r when she decides whether to specialize.) In other words, we have a classic hold-up problem. Now suppose B and S are integrated. Then the specialization decision is made by the boss of B, who maximizes total profit plus her private benefits w. So specialization will occur at date 1 if and only (3.2) v + w > r. Of course, this is also the first-best rule. We conclude that in the simple case where there is only one buyer and one seller integration is superior to nonintegration. The total net surplus under integration is given by E Max (v + w, r) - k, where the expectation is taken with respect to the probability distribution of (v, w, r).

24 22 Two buyers Let us consider next what happens if we have two buyers in the output market: call them B1, B2. We assume that a second unit of capacity is available in the input market at the same cost k as the first unit. A key question is whether there should be two units of capacity or just one (in which case supply is obviously available ex post to only one buyer). We already know that conditional on two units of capacity being available the first-best can be achieved by having B1, B2 each vertically integrate with a supplier. This is illustrated in Figure 5 (i). On the other hand, if there is only one unit of capacity, then there are two leading organizational forms, also illustrated in Figure 5. In (ii), B1, B2 and a single S all merge. In (iii), B1, B2 and a single S all stay separate ============ Figure 5 here ============ As in Section 2, an important aspect of organizational form concerns the identity of the boss. To simplify matters we will suppose that in (ii) B1, B2 and S are run by a professional manager, while in (iii) each of B1, B2 and S is run by its own manager. Note also that there are two other non-leading organizational forms. First, B1 and B2 may merge horizontally with S staying independent. Second, B1 and S may merge vertically, with B2 staying independent (or vice versa). We will return to these two forms below. We suppose that Coasian bargaining ensures that organizational form is chosen at the beginning of the period to maximize the expected value of total surplus. Implicit in this assumption is the idea that organizational form, and capacity, are contractible. That is, if, say (i) is optimal, then B1 or B2 cannot (separately) sell off some of their capacity after organizational form has been determined. And if, say, (iii) is optimal, one of the buyers cannot merge (secretly) with S An alternative assumption is made in (part of) Bolton and Whinston (1993). We return to this in footnote 14.

Vision and Firm Scope. Oliver Hart (Harvard University and NBER) and. Bengt Holmstrom (MIT and NBER) January 2002* [revised, March 6, 2002]

Vision and Firm Scope. Oliver Hart (Harvard University and NBER) and. Bengt Holmstrom (MIT and NBER) January 2002* [revised, March 6, 2002] Vision and Firm Scope by Oliver Hart (Harvard University and NBER) and Bengt Holmstrom (MIT and NBER) January 2002* [revised, March 6, 2002] *The material in this paper formed part of the first author

More information

Incomplete Contracts and Ownership: Some New Thoughts. Oliver Hart and John Moore*

Incomplete Contracts and Ownership: Some New Thoughts. Oliver Hart and John Moore* Incomplete Contracts and Ownership: Some New Thoughts by Oliver Hart and John Moore* Since Ronald Coase s famous 1937 article (Coase (1937)), economists have grappled with the question of what characterizes

More information

Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2018 1 / 36 Coase (1937) If the market is an efficient method of resource allocation, as argued by neoclassical economics, then why do so many transactions

More information

Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Coase (1937) If the market is an efficient method of resource allocation, as argued by neoclassical economics, then why do so many transactions

More information

Rethinking Incomplete Contracts

Rethinking Incomplete Contracts Rethinking Incomplete Contracts By Oliver Hart Chicago November, 2010 It is generally accepted that the contracts that parties even sophisticated ones -- write are often significantly incomplete. Some

More information

Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Definition of Incomplete Contracts Definition of Incomplete Contracts Susheng Wang 1 2 nd edition 2 July 2016 This note defines incomplete contracts and explains simple contracts. Although widely used in practice, incomplete contracts have

More information

Diskussionsbeiträge des Fachbereichs Wirtschaftswissenschaft der Freien Universität Berlin. The allocation of authority under limited liability

Diskussionsbeiträge des Fachbereichs Wirtschaftswissenschaft der Freien Universität Berlin. The allocation of authority under limited liability Diskussionsbeiträge des Fachbereichs Wirtschaftswissenschaft der Freien Universität Berlin Nr. 2005/25 VOLKSWIRTSCHAFTLICHE REIHE The allocation of authority under limited liability Kerstin Puschke ISBN

More information

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Chapter 33: Public Goods Chapter 33: Public Goods 33.1: Introduction Some people regard the message of this chapter that there are problems with the private provision of public goods as surprising or depressing. But the message

More information

Endogenous Transaction Cost, Specialization, and Strategic Alliance

Endogenous Transaction Cost, Specialization, and Strategic Alliance Endogenous Transaction Cost, Specialization, and Strategic Alliance Juyan Zhang Research Institute of Economics and Management Southwestern University of Finance and Economics Yi Zhang School of Economics

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 5. Property Rights Theory. The key question we are staring from is: What are ownership/property rights?

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 5. Property Rights Theory. The key question we are staring from is: What are ownership/property rights? Leonardo Felli 15 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 5 Property Rights Theory The key question we are staring from is: What are ownership/property rights? For an answer we need to distinguish

More information

ECON 4245 ECONOMICS OF THE FIRM

ECON 4245 ECONOMICS OF THE FIRM ECON 4245 ECONOMICS OF THE FIRM Course content Why do firms exist? And why do some firms cease to exist? How are firms financed? How are firms managed? These questions are analysed by using various models

More information

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Corporate Control. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Corporate Control Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Managerial Discipline and Takeovers Managers often don t maximize the value of the firm; either because they are not capable

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 These notes have been used and commented on before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please

More information

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk

Chapter 23: Choice under Risk Chapter 23: Choice under Risk 23.1: Introduction We consider in this chapter optimal behaviour in conditions of risk. By this we mean that, when the individual takes a decision, he or she does not know

More information

The inadequacy of specificity and role of importance in explaining hold-up

The inadequacy of specificity and role of importance in explaining hold-up The inadequacy of specificity and role of importance in explaining hold-up Jakob Lage Hansen LINK Department of Industrial Economics and Strategy Copenhagen Business School Howitzvej 60, 2000 Frederiksberg,

More information

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014 HARVARD UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS General Examination in Microeconomic Theory SPRING 2014 You have FOUR hours. Answer all questions Those taking the FINAL have THREE hours Part A (Glaeser): 55

More information

Economics and Computation

Economics and Computation Economics and Computation ECON 425/563 and CPSC 455/555 Professor Dirk Bergemann and Professor Joan Feigenbaum Reputation Systems In case of any questions and/or remarks on these lecture notes, please

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 3: Strategic Form Games - Solution Concepts Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 9, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory

Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercises Solutions: Game Theory Exercise. (U, R).. (U, L) and (D, R). 3. (D, R). 4. (U, L) and (D, R). 5. First, eliminate R as it is strictly dominated by M for player. Second, eliminate M as it is strictly

More information

Asset specificity and holdups. Benjamin Klein 1

Asset specificity and holdups. Benjamin Klein 1 Asset specificity and holdups Benjamin Klein 1 Specific assets are assets that have a significantly higher value within a particular transacting relationship than outside the relationship. To illustrate,

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 6. Separation of Ownership and Control

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 6. Separation of Ownership and Control Leonardo Felli 16 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 6 Separation of Ownership and Control The definition of ownership considered is limited to an environment in which the whole ownership

More information

Public-private Partnerships in Micro-finance: Should NGO Involvement be Restricted?

Public-private Partnerships in Micro-finance: Should NGO Involvement be Restricted? MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Public-private Partnerships in Micro-finance: Should NGO Involvement be Restricted? Prabal Roy Chowdhury and Jaideep Roy Indian Statistical Institute, Delhi Center and

More information

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments 6.1: Introduction This chapter and the next contain almost identical analyses concerning the supply and demand implied by different kinds

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 8: Bargaining + Theory of the Firm 1 Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics December 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 8: Bargaining + Theory of the Firm 1 Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics December 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 8: Bargaining + Theory of the Firm 1 Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics December 2016 1 Axiomatic bargaining theory Before noncooperative bargaining theory, there was

More information

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance ECON 522 - DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW I Contracts When we were studying property law we were looking at situations in which the exchange of goods/services takes place at the time of trade, but sometimes

More information

Internet Appendix for Financial Contracting and Organizational Form: Evidence from the Regulation of Trade Credit

Internet Appendix for Financial Contracting and Organizational Form: Evidence from the Regulation of Trade Credit Internet Appendix for Financial Contracting and Organizational Form: Evidence from the Regulation of Trade Credit This Internet Appendix containes information and results referred to but not included in

More information

Rural Financial Intermediaries

Rural Financial Intermediaries Rural Financial Intermediaries 1. Limited Liability, Collateral and Its Substitutes 1 A striking empirical fact about the operation of rural financial markets is how markedly the conditions of access can

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

Quarterly Journal of Economics, CXIII(2), May, INSECURE PROPERTY RIGHTS AND GOVERNMENT OWNERSHIP OF FIRMS *

Quarterly Journal of Economics, CXIII(2), May, INSECURE PROPERTY RIGHTS AND GOVERNMENT OWNERSHIP OF FIRMS * Quarterly Journal of Economics, CXIII(2), May, 1998. INSECURE PROPERTY RIGHTS AND GOVERNMENT OWNERSHIP OF FIRMS * Jiahua Che Department of Economics University of Notre Dame and Yingyi Qian Department

More information

Trade Agreements and the Nature of Price Determination

Trade Agreements and the Nature of Price Determination Trade Agreements and the Nature of Price Determination By POL ANTRÀS AND ROBERT W. STAIGER The terms-of-trade theory of trade agreements holds that governments are attracted to trade agreements as a means

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

CONTRACT THEORY. Patrick Bolton and Mathias Dewatripont. The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

CONTRACT THEORY. Patrick Bolton and Mathias Dewatripont. The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England r CONTRACT THEORY Patrick Bolton and Mathias Dewatripont The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England Preface xv 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Optimal Employment Contracts without Uncertainty, Hidden

More information

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory

Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory Week 8: Basic concepts in game theory Part 1: Examples of games We introduce here the basic objects involved in game theory. To specify a game ones gives The players. The set of all possible strategies

More information

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Online Appendix for Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Giacomo Rodano Bank of Italy Nicolas Serrano-Velarde Bocconi University December 23, 2014 Emanuele Tarantino University of Mannheim 1 1 Reorganization,

More information

Holdup: Investment Dynamics, Bargaining and Gradualism

Holdup: Investment Dynamics, Bargaining and Gradualism Holdup: Investment Dynamics, Bargaining and Gradualism Indian Statistical Institute, Lincoln University, University of Sydney October, 2011 (Work in Progress) Holdup: Motivating example What is holdup?

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 24, 2016 Announcements Homework #4 is due next week. Review of Last Lecture In extensive games with imperfect information,

More information

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercise - Quantity competition 1 Take firm 1 s perspective Total revenue is R(q 1 = (4 q 1 q q 1 and, hence, marginal revenue is MR 1 (q 1 = 4 q 1 q Marginal cost is MC

More information

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati Module No. # 03 Illustrations of Nash Equilibrium Lecture No. # 04

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

Credible Threats, Reputation and Private Monitoring.

Credible Threats, Reputation and Private Monitoring. Credible Threats, Reputation and Private Monitoring. Olivier Compte First Version: June 2001 This Version: November 2003 Abstract In principal-agent relationships, a termination threat is often thought

More information

Moral Hazard: Dynamic Models. Preliminary Lecture Notes

Moral Hazard: Dynamic Models. Preliminary Lecture Notes Moral Hazard: Dynamic Models Preliminary Lecture Notes Hongbin Cai and Xi Weng Department of Applied Economics, Guanghua School of Management Peking University November 2014 Contents 1 Static Moral Hazard

More information

January 26,

January 26, January 26, 2015 Exercise 9 7.c.1, 7.d.1, 7.d.2, 8.b.1, 8.b.2, 8.b.3, 8.b.4,8.b.5, 8.d.1, 8.d.2 Example 10 There are two divisions of a firm (1 and 2) that would benefit from a research project conducted

More information

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations 19.1: Introduction This chapter is interesting and important. It also helps to answer a question you may well have been asking ever since we studied quasi-linear

More information

Delegation of Decision-Making in Organizations. Margaret A. Meyer Nuffield College and Department of Economics Oxford University

Delegation of Decision-Making in Organizations. Margaret A. Meyer Nuffield College and Department of Economics Oxford University Delegation of Decision-Making in Organizations Margaret A. Meyer Nuffield College and Department of Economics Oxford University 2017 What determines the degree to which decision-making is centralized (concentrated

More information

Appendices. A Simple Model of Contagion in Venture Capital

Appendices. A Simple Model of Contagion in Venture Capital Appendices A A Simple Model of Contagion in Venture Capital Given the structure of venture capital financing just described, the potential mechanisms by which shocks might propagate across companies in

More information

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium

Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium Chapter 11 Iterated Dominance and Nash Equilibrium In the previous chapter we examined simultaneous move games in which each player had a dominant strategy; the Prisoner s Dilemma game was one example.

More information

1 Ricardian Neutrality of Fiscal Policy

1 Ricardian Neutrality of Fiscal Policy 1 Ricardian Neutrality of Fiscal Policy We start our analysis of fiscal policy by stating a neutrality result for fiscal policy which is due to David Ricardo (1817), and whose formal illustration is due

More information

Other Regarding Preferences

Other Regarding Preferences Other Regarding Preferences Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Spring 015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University 1 Lecture 1 We are now going to introduce two models of other regarding preferences, and think

More information

Delegated Monitoring, Legal Protection, Runs and Commitment

Delegated Monitoring, Legal Protection, Runs and Commitment Delegated Monitoring, Legal Protection, Runs and Commitment Douglas W. Diamond MIT (visiting), Chicago Booth and NBER FTG Summer School, St. Louis August 14, 2015 1 The Public Project 1 Project 2 Firm

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016 More on strategic games and extensive games with perfect information Block 2 Jun 11, 2017 Auctions results Histogram of

More information

Auctions. Agenda. Definition. Syllabus: Mansfield, chapter 15 Jehle, chapter 9

Auctions. Agenda. Definition. Syllabus: Mansfield, chapter 15 Jehle, chapter 9 Auctions Syllabus: Mansfield, chapter 15 Jehle, chapter 9 1 Agenda Types of auctions Bidding behavior Buyer s maximization problem Seller s maximization problem Introducing risk aversion Winner s curse

More information

Chapter 1 Microeconomics of Consumer Theory

Chapter 1 Microeconomics of Consumer Theory Chapter Microeconomics of Consumer Theory The two broad categories of decision-makers in an economy are consumers and firms. Each individual in each of these groups makes its decisions in order to achieve

More information

1 Ricardian Neutrality of Fiscal Policy

1 Ricardian Neutrality of Fiscal Policy 1 Ricardian Neutrality of Fiscal Policy For a long time, when economists thought about the effect of government debt on aggregate output, they focused on the so called crowding-out effect. To simplify

More information

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6

m 11 m 12 Non-Zero Sum Games Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games R&N Section 17.6 Non-Zero Sum Games R&N Section 17.6 Matrix Form of Zero-Sum Games m 11 m 12 m 21 m 22 m ij = Player A s payoff if Player A follows pure strategy i and Player B follows pure strategy j 1 Results so far

More information

Chapter 3 Dynamic Consumption-Savings Framework

Chapter 3 Dynamic Consumption-Savings Framework Chapter 3 Dynamic Consumption-Savings Framework We just studied the consumption-leisure model as a one-shot model in which individuals had no regard for the future: they simply worked to earn income, all

More information

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment

Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment Competing Mechanisms with Limited Commitment Suehyun Kwon CESIFO WORKING PAPER NO. 6280 CATEGORY 12: EMPIRICAL AND THEORETICAL METHODS DECEMBER 2016 An electronic version of the paper may be downloaded

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 14, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Review Examples of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria Mixed Strategies

More information

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Bayesian Nash Equilibrium We have already seen that a strategy for a player in a game of incomplete information is a function that specifies what action or actions to take in the game, for every possibletypeofthatplayer.

More information

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium

ANASH EQUILIBRIUM of a strategic game is an action profile in which every. Strategy Equilibrium Draft chapter from An introduction to game theory by Martin J. Osborne. Version: 2002/7/23. Martin.Osborne@utoronto.ca http://www.economics.utoronto.ca/osborne Copyright 1995 2002 by Martin J. Osborne.

More information

Entry Barriers. Özlem Bedre-Defolie. July 6, European School of Management and Technology

Entry Barriers. Özlem Bedre-Defolie. July 6, European School of Management and Technology Entry Barriers Özlem Bedre-Defolie European School of Management and Technology July 6, 2018 Bedre-Defolie (ESMT) Entry Barriers July 6, 2018 1 / 36 Exclusive Customer Contacts (No Downstream Competition)

More information

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome.

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome. AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED Alex Gershkov and Flavio Toxvaerd November 2004. Preliminary, comments welcome. Abstract. This paper revisits recent empirical research on buyer credulity

More information

Microeconomics (Uncertainty & Behavioural Economics, Ch 05)

Microeconomics (Uncertainty & Behavioural Economics, Ch 05) Microeconomics (Uncertainty & Behavioural Economics, Ch 05) Lecture 23 Apr 10, 2017 Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior To examine the ways that people can compare and choose among risky alternatives, we

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 2017 Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Exam date: June 5, 07. (40 points) Consider a Cournot duopoly. The market price is given by q q, where q and q are the quantities of output produced

More information

Chapter 19 Optimal Fiscal Policy

Chapter 19 Optimal Fiscal Policy Chapter 19 Optimal Fiscal Policy We now proceed to study optimal fiscal policy. We should make clear at the outset what we mean by this. In general, fiscal policy entails the government choosing its spending

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 23, 2015 Administrative Stuff Homework 2 is due next week. Due to the change in material covered, I have decided to change the grading system

More information

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions.

ECON Microeconomics II IRYNA DUDNYK. Auctions. Auctions. What is an auction? When and whhy do we need auctions? Auction is a mechanism of allocating a particular object at a certain price. Allocating part concerns who will get the object and the price

More information

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011

Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011 Financial Economics Field Exam August 2011 There are two questions on the exam, representing Macroeconomic Finance (234A) and Corporate Finance (234C). Please answer both questions to the best of your

More information

Trade Agreements as Endogenously Incomplete Contracts

Trade Agreements as Endogenously Incomplete Contracts Trade Agreements as Endogenously Incomplete Contracts Henrik Horn (Research Institute of Industrial Economics, Stockholm) Giovanni Maggi (Princeton University) Robert W. Staiger (Stanford University and

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES HOLD-UP, ASSET OWNERSHIP, AND REFERENCE POINTS. Oliver Hart. Working Paper

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES HOLD-UP, ASSET OWNERSHIP, AND REFERENCE POINTS. Oliver Hart. Working Paper NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES HOLD-UP, ASSET OWNERSHIP, AND REFERENCE POINTS Oliver Hart Working Paper 13540 http://www.nber.org/papers/w13540 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue

More information

OWNERSHIP AND RESIDUAL RIGHTS OF CONTROL Ownership is usually considered the best way to incentivize economic agents:

OWNERSHIP AND RESIDUAL RIGHTS OF CONTROL Ownership is usually considered the best way to incentivize economic agents: OWNERSHIP AND RESIDUAL RIGHTS OF CONTROL Ownership is usually considered the best way to incentivize economic agents: To create To protect To increase The value of their own assets 1 How can ownership

More information

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation

Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Lecture 5 Leadership and Reputation Reputations arise in situations where there is an element of repetition, and also where coordination between players is possible. One definition of leadership is that

More information

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013.

Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Econ 101A Final exam May 14, 2013. Do not turn the page until instructed to. Do not forget to write Problems 1 in the first Blue Book and Problems 2, 3 and 4 in the second Blue Book. 1 Econ 101A Final

More information

Relational Contracts and the Theory of the Firm: A Renegotiation-Proof Approach

Relational Contracts and the Theory of the Firm: A Renegotiation-Proof Approach Relational Contracts and the Theory of the Firm: A Renegotiation-Proof Approach M. Deniz Yavuz January 15, 2007 deniz.yavuz@asu.edu, Arizona State University. I would like to thank Benjamin Polak for his

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012 The Revenue Equivalence Theorem Note: This is a only a draft

More information

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions? March 3, 215 Steven A. Matthews, A Technical Primer on Auction Theory I: Independent Private Values, Northwestern University CMSEMS Discussion Paper No. 196, May, 1995. This paper is posted on the course

More information

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants April 2008 Abstract In this paper, we determine the optimal exercise strategy for corporate warrants if investors suffer from

More information

Attracting Intra-marginal Traders across Multiple Markets

Attracting Intra-marginal Traders across Multiple Markets Attracting Intra-marginal Traders across Multiple Markets Jung-woo Sohn, Sooyeon Lee, and Tracy Mullen College of Information Sciences and Technology, The Pennsylvania State University, University Park,

More information

Ricardo. The Model. Ricardo s model has several assumptions:

Ricardo. The Model. Ricardo s model has several assumptions: Ricardo Ricardo as you will have read was a very smart man. He developed the first model of trade that affected the discussion of international trade from 1820 to the present day. Crucial predictions of

More information

October 9. The problem of ties (i.e., = ) will not matter here because it will occur with probability

October 9. The problem of ties (i.e., = ) will not matter here because it will occur with probability October 9 Example 30 (1.1, p.331: A bargaining breakdown) There are two people, J and K. J has an asset that he would like to sell to K. J s reservation value is 2 (i.e., he profits only if he sells it

More information

Relational Incentive Contracts

Relational Incentive Contracts Relational Incentive Contracts Jonathan Levin May 2006 These notes consider Levin s (2003) paper on relational incentive contracts, which studies how self-enforcing contracts can provide incentives in

More information

A study on the significance of game theory in mergers & acquisitions pricing

A study on the significance of game theory in mergers & acquisitions pricing 2016; 2(6): 47-53 ISSN Print: 2394-7500 ISSN Online: 2394-5869 Impact Factor: 5.2 IJAR 2016; 2(6): 47-53 www.allresearchjournal.com Received: 11-04-2016 Accepted: 12-05-2016 Yonus Ahmad Dar PhD Scholar

More information

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation Journal of Economics and Finance Volume 24 Number 1 Spring 2000 Pages 56-63 Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation Veronika Grimm and Ulrich Schmidt* Abstract This paper considers the classical independent

More information

Solution to Tutorial 1

Solution to Tutorial 1 Solution to Tutorial 1 011/01 Semester I MA464 Game Theory Tutor: Xiang Sun August 4, 011 1 Review Static means one-shot, or simultaneous-move; Complete information means that the payoff functions are

More information

Christiano 362, Winter 2006 Lecture #3: More on Exchange Rates More on the idea that exchange rates move around a lot.

Christiano 362, Winter 2006 Lecture #3: More on Exchange Rates More on the idea that exchange rates move around a lot. Christiano 362, Winter 2006 Lecture #3: More on Exchange Rates More on the idea that exchange rates move around a lot. 1.Theexampleattheendoflecture#2discussedalargemovementin the US-Japanese exchange

More information

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations?

d. Find a competitive equilibrium for this economy. Is the allocation Pareto efficient? Are there any other competitive equilibrium allocations? Answers to Microeconomics Prelim of August 7, 0. Consider an individual faced with two job choices: she can either accept a position with a fixed annual salary of x > 0 which requires L x units of labor

More information

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory

Solution to Tutorial /2013 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory Solution to Tutorial 1 01/013 Semester I MA464 Game Theory Tutor: Xiang Sun August 30, 01 1 Review Static means one-shot, or simultaneous-move; Complete information means that the payoff functions are

More information

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Ahmer Tarar Department of Political Science Texas A&M University 4348 TAMU College Station, TX 77843-4348 email: ahmertarar@pols.tamu.edu

More information

Chapter 9 The IS LM FE Model: A General Framework for Macroeconomic Analysis

Chapter 9 The IS LM FE Model: A General Framework for Macroeconomic Analysis Chapter 9 The IS LM FE Model: A General Framework for Macroeconomic Analysis The main goal of Chapter 8 was to describe business cycles by presenting the business cycle facts. This and the following three

More information

2c Tax Incidence : General Equilibrium

2c Tax Incidence : General Equilibrium 2c Tax Incidence : General Equilibrium Partial equilibrium tax incidence misses out on a lot of important aspects of economic activity. Among those aspects : markets are interrelated, so that prices of

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

Chapter 7 Review questions

Chapter 7 Review questions Chapter 7 Review questions 71 What is the Nash equilibrium in a dictator game? What about the trust game and ultimatum game? Be careful to distinguish sub game perfect Nash equilibria from other Nash equilibria

More information

ECO410H: Practice Questions 2 SOLUTIONS

ECO410H: Practice Questions 2 SOLUTIONS ECO410H: Practice Questions SOLUTIONS 1. (a) The unique Nash equilibrium strategy profile is s = (M, M). (b) The unique Nash equilibrium strategy profile is s = (R4, C3). (c) The two Nash equilibria are

More information

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion?

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion? Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion? Patrick Rey and Michael D. Whinston 1 Introduction In a recent paper, Marx and Shaffer (2007) study a model of vertical contracting between a manufacturer and two

More information

IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND TRADE POLICY

IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND TRADE POLICY IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND TRADE POLICY Once there is imperfect competition in trade models, what happens if trade policies are introduced? A literature has grown up around this, often described as strategic

More information

Simple Notes on the ISLM Model (The Mundell-Fleming Model)

Simple Notes on the ISLM Model (The Mundell-Fleming Model) Simple Notes on the ISLM Model (The Mundell-Fleming Model) This is a model that describes the dynamics of economies in the short run. It has million of critiques, and rightfully so. However, even though

More information

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #14: Robust Price-of-Anarchy Bounds in Smooth Games Tim Roughgarden November 6, 013 1 Canonical POA Proofs In Lecture 1 we proved that the price of anarchy (POA)

More information

Section 9, Chapter 2 Moral Hazard and Insurance

Section 9, Chapter 2 Moral Hazard and Insurance September 24 additional problems due Tuesday, Sept. 29: p. 194: 1, 2, 3 0.0.12 Section 9, Chapter 2 Moral Hazard and Insurance Section 9.1 is a lengthy and fact-filled discussion of issues of information

More information

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3 Introduction to Political Economy 14.770 Problem Set 3 Due date: Question 1: Consider an alternative model of lobbying (compared to the Grossman and Helpman model with enforceable contracts), where lobbies

More information