Victim or injurer, small car or SUV: Tort liability rules under role-type uncertainty

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Victim or injurer, small car or SUV: Tort liability rules under role-type uncertainty"

Transcription

1 International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) Victim or injurer, small car or SUV: Tort liability rules under role-type uncertainty Jeonghyun Kim a, Allan M. Feldman b, a Fair Competition Policy Division, Korea Information Society Development Institute, Kwachun, Kyunggi-Do , Korea b Department of Economics, Brown University, Providence, RI 02906, United States Abstract In this paper we modify the standard tort model by introducing role-type uncertainty. That is, we assume that neither party knows in advance whether she will be the victim or the injurer when an accident occurs. When the standards of care of the two parties are set at the socially optimal levels, only pure comparative negligence and the equal division rule guarantee efficiency, while the rules of simple negligence, contributory negligence, and comparative negligence with fixed division (other than a 50:50 split) may produce inefficient equilibria. Since pure comparative negligence splits liability between negligent parties according to each party s degree of fault, it makes the accident loss division independent of one s role-type. This produces its efficiency advantage. We extend the model to the choice of vehicle size, as a factor determining who will be the injurer and who the victim in motor vehicle collisions. In the extension we analyze various standard negligencebased liability rules, and tax rules, as instruments to mitigate inefficiency resulting from the vehicle size arms race. We also examine two strict liability rules, one of which incorporates a comparative negligence feature; this rule prevents inefficiency from both role-type uncertainty and from the arms race Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. JEL classification: K13; D61 Keywords: Role-type uncertainty; Negligence; Comparative negligence; Contributory negligence; Equal division rule; Motor vehicle collisions; Vehicle size Corresponding author. addresses: sowoonsr@kisdi.re.kr (J. Kim), Allan Feldman@Brown.edu (A.M. Feldman) /$ see front matter 2007 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi: /j.irle

2 456 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) Introduction One of the stylized features of the standard economic model of tort law is that each party s potential role as a victim or an injurer in a possible accident is pre-determined. That is, each knows in advance the position victim or injurer she will be in if an event occurs that leads to a lawsuit. This set-up is consistent with some types of torts, such as product liability, medical malpractice, and slip and fall cases. But it may not fit some other types of torts. For example, when motor vehicles collide, there is great uncertainty about which party or parties will sustain serious injury. Since a seriously injured party is more likely to file a lawsuit than an uninjured or slightly injured party, which party will be plaintiff and which will be defendant (that is, which will be victim and which injurer) is extremely uncertain ex ante. 1 Hunting accidents may be similar: when A and B head to the woods, and A shoots B, mistaking him for a deer, they probably had no prior belief that B would be the victim and A the injurer. Similarly, if two fishing vessels collide and one sinks, the captains probably had no good knowledge beforehand about which vessel would sink and which would not, which party would be the victim and which would be the injurer. Arlen (1990) extends the standard analysis, of one harmed party and advanced knowledge of who will be victim and who injurer, to the bilateral risk situation in which injurers as well as victims suffer accident damages. 2 She shows that if each party is allowed to sue her counterpart for her own damages, the main implications of the basic model remain intact. That is, various forms of negligence-based rules 3 induce both parties to take efficient levels of care if the standard of care for each party is set equal to the socially efficient level. In her model, however, the proportion of total damages each party would suffer from an accident is known in advance. Landes and Posner (1987, p. 77) and Wittman, Friedman, Crevier, and Braskin (1997) make the same assumption in dealing with the theory of bilateral risk accidents. 4 But this does not capture the essential uncertainty about whether a party will be the victim or the injurer. Our paper modifies the standard tort model by introducing role-type uncertainty. As in the standard model, we will assume that only one party will be harmed. 5 But we will also 1 According to a study of the U.S. Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, automobile accidents or property liability claims accounted for more than 75% of all tort filings in state courts between July 1, 1991 and June 30, Medical malpractice, product liability, and toxic substances together comprised about 10% of all the cases filed. See Cooter and Ulen (2000, pp ). Huber (1988) estimated that traffic accident claims account for around 40% of all tort cases. 2 Note that a unilateral risk model with role-type uncertainty is in essence similar to a bilateral risk model, if we assume that everyone is entitled to sue the other party for his own damages from an accident. In other words, the situation where we know that the victim suffers the whole damages but do not know who will be the victim, is analytically similar to the situation where we know both can suffer damages but do not know what the proportions will be. 3 Arlen (1990) does not include comparative negligence in her analysis. 4 White (1989) has a different approach for modeling automobile accidents cases, along the lines of Diamond (1974). Rather than considering gaming behavior between the two parties involved, she focuses on the representative driver s behavior, assuming that the other driver s care level is randomly chosen from a population. Her analysis also includes uncertainty in the court s decision-making. 5 Alternatively we could assume both parties might be harmed, but with proportions falling on the two parties not known in advance. This makes the treatment more complex.

3 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) assume that the parties do not know in advance who will be the harmed party. With this kind of imperfect information, each party makes choices based on a subjective belief about the probability that she will be the victim. Other tort uncertainties have been explored by other authors. Cooter and Ulen (1986) and Haddock and Curran (1985) argue that comparative negligence is superior to contributory negligence under evidentiary uncertainty, that is, uncertainty created by the imperfect ability of courts to evaluate care levels. However, Edlin (1994) argues that even with evidentiary uncertainty, if the standards of care are appropriately chosen (at levels different from the efficient levels), both negligence rules can lead to efficient outcomes. Various authors have modeled uncertainty created by heterogeneous agents. In particular, Rubinfeld (1987) and Emons (1990) introduce heterogeneity in individuals care-taking costs. They show that a properly designed sharing rule (that is, a comparative negligence rule) can improve on all-ornothing type negligence rules. But recently, Bar-Gill and Ben-Shahar (2003) critique these approaches, and show with simulations that comparative negligence may be less efficient that simple negligence or contributory negligence, depending on the degree of evidentiary uncertainty. Our model abstracts from evidentiary uncertainty and heterogeneous agent uncertainty, and focuses instead on the uncertainty about which party will end up as the victim and which the injurer, that is, role-type uncertainty. In Section 2 of this paper we show that, if the two parties subjective victimization probabilities do not sum to 1, pure comparative negligence, and the equal division rule, have better efficiency properties than other standard negligence-based rules. We show that role-type uncertainty strengthens the efficiency claims of pure comparative negligence and the equal division rule, because they make the liability assignments between two negligent parties independent of their role-types. In contrast, the rules of simple negligence, negligence with contributory negligence as a defense, and comparative negligence with a fixed division other than 50:50, all allow the possibility of inefficient equilibria in which both parties take insufficient care. In Section 3 of the paper we extend the model to a theory of liability rules and choice of motor vehicle size. We continue to assume role-type uncertainty, but this is also a theory of vehicle collisions, where one s probability of being the injurer depends on the size of one s vehicle. Drivers of big cars are more likely to be injurers, and drivers of small cars, victims. Our model here is similar in spirit to White s (2004) arms race paper. The general conclusion of Section 3 is that the standard negligence-based liability rules we examined in Section 2 of the paper produce efficient equilibria in terms of the parties care levels, but all produce an inefficient arms race in terms of vehicle size. We indicate how adding a size-based standard of care could eliminate the inefficiency, and we compare that policy to the imposition of a vehicle size tax. We conclude by examining two variants of strict liability, one of which, strict liability with a defense of contributory negligence, eliminates the arms race in vehicle size, but may allow inefficiencies because of role-type uncertainty. The second, strict liability with a defense of comparative negligence, solves the arms race, and also, being a pure comparative negligence rule, guarantees efficiency in spite of role-type uncertainty. We briefly compare these proposed solutions to the legal remedies advocated by Latin and Kasolas (2002) and Case (2006).

4 458 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) Efficient liability rules under role-type uncertainty 2.1. The model Suppose that there are two risk-neutral people, X and Y, who engage in some activity that creates a risk of accidents. If an accident occurs, there is one victim, who suffers a monetary loss L > 0. The loss L is assumed to be constant. 6 But there is uncertainty regarding the roles of X and Y in the possible accident: neither knows in advance whether she will be the victim or the injurer. We assume that the uncertainty about the identity of the victim/injurer is independent of the uncertainty about whether or not an accident will occur. We assume that each party has a subjective ex ante belief about the likelihood that, if an accident occurs, she will be the victim. We define: α Person X s probability that she will be the victim, if an accident occurs. β Person Y s probability that she will be the victim, if an accident occurs. We assume that 0 α, β 1. We will call α and β the victimization probabilities, or role-type uncertainty parameters, depending on context. We assume that X and Y believe their probabilities of being the injurer are 1 α and 1 β, respectively. Because the occurrence/non-occurrence of an accident is assumed independent of the identity of the victim/injurer, party X s subjective probability of being a victim in an accident is α times the accident probability, and her subjective probability of being an injurer in an accident is 1 α times the accident probability. Since α and β are subjective probabilities, formed before the fact, and not necessarily observable by the other party, the sum of α and β need not equal 1. That is, X and Y may form their beliefs about victimization probabilities in some uncoordinated or inconsistent way. They may not share the same information or beliefs. If they had the same information and beliefs, the subjective probabilities would sum to 1. The subjective probabilities are not generally the true probabilities that X or Y will be victim. If they were true probabilities, they would of course sum to 1. It will turn out that the value of α + β has a crucial role in determining game equilibria, and the efficiency or lack thereof, of some liability rules. 7 Let x and y denote person X s and person Y s care levels, respectively, measured by their care expenditures. Following the standard modeling in tort liability literature since Brown (1973), we assume that each person can choose any level of care between 0 and, that the care levels are observable by both, and that the probability of an accident, p(x, y), is a continuous and differentiable function of the care levels, known to both. We assume that increasing care levels reduce the probability of an accident, and thus expected accident costs (p x < 0, and p y < 0). We also assume that, for all x and y, p(x, y)>0, p xx >0, p yy >0, and p xy >0. 6 The assumption of a constant L can also be relaxed, at the cost of greater complexity. 7 For example, in the context of motor vehicle collisions, each driver s vehicle is different in terms of its weight, bumper height, etc. The drivers may not know the characteristics of the other party s vehicle in advance. A Hummer driver may expect that her probability of being the victim in a collision with another vehicle will be small. If two Hummer drivers are involved in a collision, α + β may be much less than one. If two motorcycle riders are involved in a collision, α + β may be much greater than 1.

5 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) To repeat, there are two levels of uncertainty in our model; the first is whether or not an accident will occur. This is treated in the standard fashion: the probability of an accident is a function of both care levels; care levels are money expenditures, easily observable; both parties know the care levels, and therefore both know the accident probabilities. The second is role-type uncertainty: if an accident occurs, who sustains the losses? This uncertainty is modeled with the subjective victimization probabilities α and β. For simplicity, we are assuming that the care levels do not affect α and β. 8 We allow these probabilities to be highly subjective: for instance, an optimistic person may know that she has a given probability of being involved in an accident with another person, but she may believe that if she is, she has only a small chance of being hurt. The subjective victimization probabilities are generally not directly observable by the other party, and they may be inconsistent in the sense that they do not sum to 1. Total social cost (TSC) is defined as the sum of care-taking costs of both parties and expected accident costs. That is, TSC = x + y + p(x, y)l. The social goal is, as usual, to minimize total social cost. Let (x *, y * ) denote the solution to this TSC minimization problem. We will assume for the sake of clarity in this paper that (x *, y * ) is unique. 9 We call (x *, y * ) the efficient, orsocially optimal care combination. In our model, when an accident occurs the entire loss L is initially born by the victim. The court then enforces a liability rule, which determines where L ultimately falls: on the victim, on the injurer, or on both. A negligence-based liability rule is defined in terms of which parties are negligent, and if both are negligent, possibly their degrees of negligence. A party is negligent if her care expenditure falls short of the court-enforced standard of care. We assume that everyone, including the court, knows the expected loss function and the governing liability rule, that the court can solve the TSC minimization problem, and that everyone, including the court, can observe each party s care levels accurately. However, the parties and the court may not know the true probabilities that X or Y will be victim, and the subjective victimization probabilities may be known only to their owners. Note that knowledge of the true victimization probabilities is not necessary for the determination of (x *, y * ) in our model, since we are assuming that whether the victim is X or Y, the loss L is the same. Finally, we assume that the standard of care for each party is set at the socially optimal level. That is, for instance, party X is found negligent by the court if and only if she spends x < x *. 10 In this section of the paper we will analyze and compare four standard negligencebased liability rules: simple negligence (Section 2.2 below), negligence with a defense of contributory negligence (Section 2.3), comparative negligence with fixed division (Section 2.4), and pure comparative negligence (Section 2.5). In Section 3 of the paper we will consider two more liability rules, both based on strict liability, which are significantly different from the four rules discussed in this section. Our four standard rules share the 8 This assumption can also be relaxed without changing the main implications of the paper. 9 Non-uniqueness creates considerable complication in the appropriate definition of the standard of care. See for instance Jain and Singh (2002). We prefer to avoid the complication. 10 Note that the assumptions that the court knows the expected loss function, and sets the standards of care at the efficient levels, are exceedingly strong; we argue elsewhere that these assumptions, which are standard in the literature, are actually unrealistic. See Kim (2003) and Feldman and Kim (2005).

6 460 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) following properties: (i) If both parties are non-negligent, all accident costs fall on the victim. (ii) If one party is non-negligent and the other party is negligent, all accident costs fall on the negligent party. The four rules differ as follows: (iii.a) Simple negligence. If both parties are negligent, all accident costs fall on the injurer. (iii.b) Negligence with contributory negligence as a defense. If both parties are negligent, all accident costs fall on the victim. (iii.c) Comparative negligence with fixed division. If both parties are negligent, a fixed fraction of the accident costs fall on the victim, the balance on the injurer. (iii.d) Pure comparative negligence. If both parties are negligent, the accident costs are split between victim and injurer, according to degree of fault. From properties (i) and (ii) above, we can calculate person X s expected private cost function C X under role-type uncertainty, which depends on both parties care levels and on X s subjective victimization probability. Note that these equations hold for all four standard rules: If x x and y y, then C X = x + αp(x, y)l (1) If x<x and y y, then C X = x + p(x, y)l (2) If x x and y<y, then C X = x (3) Eq. (1) says that if neither party is negligent, then party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus L times the probability of an accident in which she is the victim. Eq. (2) says that if X is negligent and Y is not, then party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus L times the probability of any accident. Eq. (3) says that if X is non-negligent and Y is negligent, then party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x. Note that β does not appear in Eqs. (1) (3). Person Y s expected private cost function C Y is derived in a similar way. Eqs. (1) (3) enable us to establish that, as in the standard model with pre-determined role-type, the social optimum (x *, y * ) is a Nash equilibrium even with role-type uncertainty, under the four standard liability rules. We call this Result 1 below. Closely related Result 2 says that under the four liability rules, there is no Nash equilibrium that involves either party taking more than due care, that is, spending more than her efficient x * or y *. Proofs of both results are omitted. Result 1. With role-type uncertainty, the social optimum (x *, y * ) is a Nash equilibrium under the rules of simple negligence, contributory negligence, comparative negligence with fixed division, and pure comparative negligence. Result 2. With role-type uncertainty, nobody takes more than due care, at any possible Nash equilibrium, under the rules of simple negligence, contributory negligence, comparative negligence with fixed division, and pure comparative negligence.

7 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) Results 1 and 2 do not rule out the possibility of a Nash equilibrium in which both parties take less than due care. Since each negligence-based rule specifies a different liability assignment in this case, the parties expected cost functions vary from rule to rule. If any of the four liability rules could successfully rule out the possibility of an insufficient-careequilibrium, then (x *, y * ) would turn out to be the unique equilibrium of the game, and we would conclude that the rule is efficient in the presence of role-type uncertainty. With this in mind, we examine each of the four rules in turn Simple negligence Under the simple negligence rule, if both parties are negligent, all accident costs fall on the injurer. This gives: If x<x and y<y, then C X = x + (1 α) p(x, y)l (4.a) The equation says that if both parties are negligent, party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus L times the probability of an accident in which she is the injurer. Note that β does not appear in equation (4.a). When facing a negligent counterpart, person X s best response for minimizing her own expected cost may be either to take due care, or to choose negligence. The intuitive reason for the latter possibility is this: X may believe that she will be victim with high probability. That is, α may be close to 1. In this case the probability of an accident in which she is injurer (and liable) will be low. She will then be likely to choose an x smaller than the efficient x *. In fact, the simple negligence rule under role-type uncertainty allows the possibility of inefficient equilibria, in which both parties are choosing negligent behavior. In addition to the efficient equilibrium at (x *, y * ), the game has an inefficient equilibrium at ( x, ỹ), where x <x and ỹ<y, if the following conditions are satisfied simultaneously: x minimizes x + (1 α )p(x, ỹ)l, and ỹ minimizes y + (1 β) p( x, y)l (5) x + (1 α) p( x, ỹ)l x (6) ỹ + (1 β) p( x, ỹ)l y (7) Expression (5) says that the chosen expenditure levels minimize the respective expected private cost expressions C X and C Y, contingent on both parties choosing to be negligent. Expressions (6) and (7) permit the parties to rationally choose a negligent x <x (and ỹ<y ), at a cost less than or equal the cost of being non-negligent. Here is a simple, if extreme, example: Suppose that party X believes that she will be the victim, and that Y believes she will be the victim (i.e., both are extreme pessimists; α = β = 1). In this case, the simple negligence game has two Nash equilibria; (0, 0) and (x *, y * ). One possible outcome in the game is an inefficient equilibrium, where neither party takes any precaution. Note that this outcome does not require irrational behavior: at (0, 0) each party is minimizing her expected costs, given the care level of the other party and given the legal rule. Nor are we assuming that that party X is so silly she thinks her probability of being victim, plus her probability of being injurer, add up to something other than 1. The odd thing about the (0, 0) equilibrium is that it is based on extreme and highly uncoordinated

8 462 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) subjective victimization probabilities. However, the victimization probabilities need not be as extreme as we assumed (α = β = 1), in fact α and β might both be substantially less than 1, and we might still have an insufficient-care Nash equilibrium. The crucial assumption in the example, as we will see in the next result, is that the two parties X and Y do not have coordinated or consistent views about the probabilities of who will be victim and who injurer; because if their views were coordinated, we would have α + β =1. A subtle objection might be made to the (0, 0) Nash equilibrium: If party X sees party Y choosing care level y =0,X can infer that Y s β must be 1. Similarly, if party Y sees party X choosing care level x =0, Y can infer that X s α must be 1. That is, the two parties can infer that their subjective victimization probabilities are inconsistent; that α + β > 1. (The inference about the other person s subjective victimization probability can generally be made if they are at an inefficient Nash equilibrium, but not if they are at the efficient Nash equilibrium.) But it is unclear what they would do with this information: Should party X, after having calculated what β must be based on her observation of y, abandon her own belief about α? Should the two parties modify their victimization probabilities in some Bayesian fashion? The answers to these questions are not obvious, and we will therefore make the simplest assumption: Party X, if she is able to compute party Y s β from an observation of Y s care level, will neither modify nor abandon her own α in the interest of making the victimization probabilities consistent. Our model can therefore be viewed as one with friction in beliefs about victimization probabilities; X and Y are quick to see and act on each other s care levels, but they are slow to discover and act on inconsistencies in beliefs about victimization probabilities. Result 3 below provides a necessary condition for the existence of an inefficient equilibrium, in terms of the sum of two subjective victimization probabilities. Result 3. α + β >1is a necessary condition for the simple negligence rule to produce an inefficient equilibrium under role-type uncertainty. Proof. Let ( x, ỹ) be an inefficient equilibrium. We will show α + β >1. By adding together inequalities (6) and (7),wehave x + ỹ + (2 (α + β))p( x, ỹ)l x + y. But since x * and y * solve the total social cost minimization problem, x + y <x + y + p(x,y )L x + ỹ + p( x, ỹ)l. Therefore x + ỹ + (2 (α + β))p( x, ỹ)l x + y < x + ỹ + p( x, ỹ)l, which implies 1 < α + β. Q.E.D Contributory negligence Under the rule of negligence with contributory negligence as a defense, the victim recovers damages from a negligent injurer, unless the victim is also negligent, in which case the losses stay with the victim. Therefore, if both parties are negligent, all accident costs fall on the victim. This gives: If x<x and y<y, then C X = x + αp(x, y)l (4.b) The equation says that if both parties are negligent, party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus L times the probability of an accident in which she is the victim. Note that β does not appear in equation (4.b).

9 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) By the same logic as was used in the preceding section, one can derive conditions for the existence of an inefficient equilibrium at ( x, ỹ), where x <x and ỹ<y. The conditions are similar to conditions (5) (7) above, and will not be given here. Like the simple negligence rule, the contributory negligence rule does not necessarily lead to an efficient outcome under role-type uncertainty. Since the accident costs fall on the victim when both are negligent, the contributory negligence rule may produce an insufficient-care equilibrium when both parties believe they have high probabilities of becoming an injurer, that is, low probabilities of becoming a victim. Here is another simple, extreme, example: Suppose that party X is sure she will be the injurer, and that Y is sure that she will be the injurer (i.e., α = β = 0). In this case, the contributory negligence game has two Nash equilibria (0, 0) and (x *, y * ), and in one neither party takes any precaution. Note that the (0, 0) is not irrational: it minimizes each party s expected costs, subject to what the other party is doing and subject to the legal rule. As in the simple negligence example discussed above, the victimization probabilities are uncoordinated or inconsistent, but we assume that even if the parties can infer that α + β < 1, they do not revise their own subjective probabilities. The important thing about this example is that it is based on uncoordinated or inconsistent beliefs about victimization probabilities; if the beliefs were coordinated we would have α + β =1. Based on the same kind of logic as used in the proof of Result 3, we have the following: Result 4. α + β < 1is a necessary condition for the contributory negligence rule to produce an inefficient equilibrium under role-type uncertainty. Result 4 makes it clear why Arlen (1990) and Wittman et al. (1997) conclude that efficiency is guaranteed under the contributory negligence rule. In their bilateral risk models, both parties suffer losses and each party s expected loss function is separable and known to everyone. Accordingly, the condition α + β = 1 (in our context) is always satisfied, and the possibility of an insufficient-care equilibrium is eliminated. Before proceeding, we will make some final remarks about Results 3 and 4. To establish each, we ask whether or not it is possible for both parties, simultaneously, to want to choose negligence. For this to happen, X must be opting for negligence while Y is being negligent, and vice versa. This requires that the expected cost to X under (X negligent, Y negligent) must be less than or equal to the expected cost to X under (X non-negligent, Y negligent), and vice versa. Since the latter expected cost is x * (or y *, respectively), we get conditions like (6) and (7) (for simply liability, with similar conditions, not shown, for contributory negligence.) We then add the two conditions together, as in the proof of Result 3, to produce our necessary condition for an inefficient equilibrium. The crucial step in that adding together is x + (1 α)p( x, ỹ)l + ỹ + (1 β)p( x, ỹ)l x + y in Result 3, with a similar inequality (used but not shown) in Result 4. What allowed this inequality to be possible for some pair ( x, ỹ) was the fact that the terms 1 α and 1 β did not have to sum to 1; if they did sum to 1, the inequality would be impossible because (x,y ) is total social cost minimizing. In this case there could be no inefficient Nash equilibrium. In short, it was the latitude created by the inclusion of the role-type uncertainty parameters, not constrained to sum to 1, in conditions (6) and (7), that led to Result 3; and similar conditions (not shown) led to Result 4. As we will see below, if the role-type uncertainty parameters could not work

10 464 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) their way into conditions analogous to (6) and (7), that latitude would disappear, and so would the inefficient Nash equilibria Comparative negligence with fixed division In contrast to all-or-nothing rules like simple negligence or contributory negligence, the comparative negligence rule with fixed division splits accident damages between two negligent parties, in some fixed proportion. 11 Let γ denote the fraction of accident damages borne by the victim when both parties are negligent (0 < γ < 1). In particular, if γ = 1/2, this is the equal division rule. The equal division rule was once the dominant doctrine in admiralty law, until it was replaced by the pure comparative negligence system. 12 Under the comparative negligence rule with fixed division, when both parties are negligent person X s expected cost function is: If x<x and y<y,c X = x + [αγ + (1 α)(1 γ)]p(x, y)l (4.c) The equation says that if both parties are negligent, party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus γl times the probability of an accident in which she is the victim, plus (1 γ)l times the probability of an accident in which she is the injurer. Note that β does not appear in equation (4.c). It is easy to see that this rule may not preclude an insufficient-care equilibrium, for certain values of α, β, and γ. The conditions for the existence of an inefficient equilibrium at ( x, ỹ), where x <x and ỹ<y, analogous to expressions (5) (7), are as follows: x minimizes x + [αγ + (1 α)(1 γ)]p(x, ỹ)l, and ỹ minimizes y + [βγ + (1 β)(1 γ)]p( x, y)l (8) x + [αγ + (1 α)(1 γ)]p( x, ỹ)l x (9) ỹ + [βγ + (1 β)(1 γ)]p( x, ỹ)l y (10) However, note that if γ = 1/2, the role-type uncertainty parameters α and β disappear in the above expressions. Moreover, under the equal division rule condition (4.c) is 11 Note that the loss-splitting property of the comparative negligence with fixed division rule works only as a defense. So this rule is different from what Shavell (1987) defines as the rule of strict division of accident losses. Strict division of accident losses implies that the fraction of losses borne by the injurer and the victim is assumed to be independent of their levels of care, and, in particular, independent of whether someone was negligent. It is straightforward that strict division of accident losses does not provide the parties with correct incentives, even in the standard model without role-type uncertainty. 12 By about 1700 English courts were consistently applying the equal division rule in admiralty collision cases. This doctrine was replaced in 1911 in Great Britain by a statute providing for division of damages in proportion to the degree of fault of each vessel. The U.S. Supreme Court adopted the equal division rule in 1854, in a ship collision case, The Schooner Catharine v. Dickinson (58 U.S. (17 how.) 170, 15L. Ed. 233). In turn, the equal division rule was replaced by the pure comparative negligence rule in U.S. admiralty cases as a result of a 1975 U.S. Supreme Court case, United States v. Reliable Transfer Co. (421 U.S. 397, 44 L. Ed. 2d 251, 95 S. Ct. 1708). See Keeton et al. (1984) and Schwartz (1994).

11 transformed to: J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) If x<x and y<y, then C X = x + 0.5p(x, y)l (4.d) That is, if both parties are negligent, then party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus one half times L times the probability of any accident. When γ = 1/2, conditions (9) and (10) become x + (1/2)p( x, ỹ)l x and ỹ + (1/2)p( x, ỹ)l y, respectively. But these two conditions cannot be satisfied simultaneously, because adding the two inequalities together yields x + ỹ + p( x, ỹ)l x + y < x + y + p(x,y )L, which is not possible, since (x *, y * ) is by assumption social cost minimizing. Therefore, the equal division rule guarantees efficiency. Note that among all fixed division rules, the equal division rule is the only one that makes one party s expected cost, assuming both parties are negligent, independent of her role-type. That is, only the equal division rule makes α and β disappear in expressions (9) and (10), and therefore eliminates the latitude that would make an inefficient equilibrium possible. All other fixed division rules allow the possibility of insufficient-care equilibria. By logic similar to that used in the proof of Result 3, we can derive a necessary condition for such equilibria: Result 5. Either (i) α + β >1 and γ<1/2, or (ii) α + β <1 and γ>1/2, is a necessary condition for the comparative negligence rule with fixed division to produce an inefficient equilibrium under role-type uncertainty. At this point we can compare simple negligence, contributory negligence, and comparative negligence with fixed division (excepting the 50:50 split) in terms of social efficiency. We find that if α + β = 1, then all three rules are efficient, but if α + β 1, none of these three rules guarantees efficiency, and, furthermore, none dominates the others on efficiency grounds Pure comparative negligence Under the pure comparative negligence rule, if both parties are negligent, accident damages are split according to degree of fault. In the context of continuous care models, the proportions of accident damages persons X and Y should bear are generally defined using the extent of each party s deviation from her due care level. That is, X s degree of fault is most naturally measured by (x * x)/(x * x + y * y), and similarly for Y s. Now, person X s expected cost function when both parties are negligent is: If x<x and y<y x x,c X = x + x x + y p(x, y)l y (4.e) The equation says that if both parties are negligent, party X s expected cost equals her care expenditure x, plus her degree of fault times L times the probability of any accident. Since neither α nor β appears in equation (4.e), when both take less than due care, each party s expected cost function is independent of the role-type uncertainty parameters. When both are negligent, one party s damage share depends only on the actual care levels, and on (x *, y * ). As before, the social optimum (x *, y * ) is a Nash equilibrium under the pure

12 466 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) comparative negligence rule. Most important, it is the unique equilibrium of the game, by an argument similar to the argument for the efficiency of the equal division rule. We leave the details to the reader. The intuition is that the degree-of-fault term in equation (4.e), pre-multiplying p(x, y)l, has no α in it; the corresponding term for party Y has no β, and the sum of the two terms, for X and Y, equals 1. In conclusion, the pure comparative negligence rule guarantees efficiency even with roletype uncertainty, as long as the standards of care are set at the socially efficient levels. Since the pure comparative negligence rule splits liability between negligent parties according to each party s degree of fault, it makes the accident loss division independent of one s role-type. No matter what α and β are, the rule produces the efficient outcome as the unique equilibrium of the game. Our main findings so far are summarized in: Proposition 1. Suppose that the standard of care for each party is set at the socially optimal level. In the standard tort model, with role-type uncertainty, under which each party forms a subjective belief regarding her probability of becoming an injurer or a victim: (i) If α + β = 1, the four standard negligence rules we have examined all guarantee efficiency. (ii) For arbitrary α and β, the pure comparative negligence rule and the equal division rule both guarantee efficiency. (iii) However, for arbitrary α and β, the rules of simple negligence, contributory negligence, and comparative negligence with fixed division (other than the 50:50 split) all produce the possibility of an inefficient equilibrium in which both parties take less than due care. Among these three rules, no rule dominates others in terms of efficiency. 3. Applying the model to collisions of different-sized vehicles At this stage we add other dimensions to the analysis. We will assume the losses stem from motor vehicle accidents. We will relate the subjective victimization probabilities α and β to the true victimization probabilities, which we will assume are based on vehicle size. Note that adding the dimension of vehicle size to our model at this point is similar to the addition of activity level, as a choice independent of, and perhaps prior to, the choice of care level, in the standard literature. 13 When activity level can vary, standard negligence-based liability rules may fail to be efficient, because they do not provide incentives to careful parties to limit the extent of their activities. On the other hand, strict liability may provide such incentives. The difference between adding activity level in the standard tort model, and adding vehicle size in our role-type uncertainty model, is this: Activity level is assumed to affect expected losses, or at least expected losses per unit time. In contrast, we assume that vehicle size has no impact on p(x, y) or on L, but only affects the (true) probabilities of who will be victim and who injurer. (We will elaborate on our use of this assumption 13 See for example Polinsky (1983), Chapter 6.

13 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) below; see footnote 14.) The interesting similarity is this: just as consideration of activity level in the standard model points toward strict liability, the problem of vehicle size in our model is solved by certain strict liability rules. With the burgeoning use of SUV s and pickup trucks as passenger vehicles in recent years, it has become apparent that many people are choosing large vehicles to reduce the likelihood that, in the event of a collision, they will be victims. If your Hummer H1 collides with my Honda Civic, whose vehicle is totaled? More important, who goes to the hospital, or worse? The auto companies don t advertise it explicitly, but it s implicit: Drive our big SUV, and you ll walk away from the crash; the guy in the other car (or his spouse or children) will be injured or killed. White (2004) provides compelling evidence about the negative effects created by vehicle size in the United States. (See also Latin and Kasolas, 2002 and Case, 2006.) Among the statistical results she reports are these: Consider a traffic collision between vehicles A and B. IfA is a car, then the probability of a fatality in A is 38% lower if B is a car rather than a light truck. If A is a light truck, then the probability of a fatality in A is 55% lower if B is a car rather than a light truck. If A is a motorcycle, then the probability of a fatality on A is 125% higher if B is a light truck rather than a car. White also provides similar data on serious injuries. White s data indicate that if 1 million light trucks on US highways were replaced by cars, traffic fatalities would fall by between 34 and 93 per year. White also discusses, in general terms, the failure of liability rules, insurance, and traffic rules to solve this externality problem. The model we present below is obviously in the same spirit as White s paper. However, we differ from her by emphasizing the game theoretic outcomes when persons X and Y are responding to each other s vehicle sizes, and are simultaneously playing the care choice liability game. Moreover, White (2004) goes far beyond claiming that the vehicle size arms race is a matter of vehicle owners attempting to throw fixed costs on the other party. In fact, she presents evidence that the upsizing of vehicles results in substantially higher totals of deaths and injuries in the US. In our model, in contrast, we assume (perhaps unrealistically) that accident probabilities, and losses when accidents occur, are not affected by vehicle size. We assume that vehicle size merely impacts on the probabilities of who will be victim. We do assume that size is costly, but only in the sense that the consumer pays a higher price for purchasing a larger vehicle. And under these quite limited assumptions, we establish that, in theory, the arms race will be very costly. 14 We now assume that there is a one-dimensional property that is chosen by each of the potential parties to accidents, which we call size. We call this size following White (2004) and others; however, what we mean is weight (that is, mass). (In reality, motor vehicles obviously have a number of characteristics that impact on the probability that 14 For the sake of simplicity we are assuming vehicle size has no impact on accident probabilities, and losses when accidents occur. White (2004) presents much evidence to the contrary (see also Latin and Kasolas (2002), and Case (2006)). In our theoretical model, we infer substantial social costs resulting from the vehicle size arms race. If larger vehicles also produce greater accident probabilities and greater losses per accident, as the evidence suggests, the social costs figured in our model underestimate the true social costs. That is, our estimate of arms race social costs provides a lower bound for the true costs.

14 468 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) their occupants will be victims or injurers, including weight, bumper and frame height, horsepower, body reinforcements and rigidity, crumple zones, airbags, and so on.) Weight is a particularly important characteristic affecting which parties in an accident may be harmed, simply because of physical laws, particularly the law of conservation of linear momentum. For instance, suppose an 8000 lb light truck collides precisely head on with a 2000 lb car, both traveling at 50 miles per hour (in opposite directions). Suppose the wrecked vehicles travel together as a single unit (rather than bouncing apart like elastic billiard balls). The resulting 2-vehicle tangle will continue to travel in the direction of the truck, at 30 m.p.h., by conservation of momentum. The occupants of the light truck will have experienced a 20 m.p.h. deceleration in the brief period of the crash, whereas the occupants of the car will have experienced an 80 m.p.h. deceleration. It is no surprise that, when a train and a car collide, the occupants of the car die much more often than the occupants of the train; the explanation is that the train is the very much more massive object. We now assume that size is a non-negative number; and we normalize the units so the smallest vehicle has size 0. (A more realistic normalization would put the minimum at 1, but this would make some of our equations later on unnecessarily complex.) We assume that person X chooses size s, and that person Y chooses size t. Note that vehicle size is a continuous variable ranging from 0 to infinity in our model. Therefore person X s vehicle size s can range continuously from Mini Cooper to Hummer H1 and beyond, and so can person Y s vehicle size t. We assume that the following equations determine the true victimization probabilities, which we will call ᾱ and β: ᾱ = t s + t and β = s (11) s + t Note that ᾱ + β = 1, as should be the case for the true probabilities. To put it another way, the true probability that person X is the injurer is given by s/(s + t), the fraction of total vehicle size comprised by X s vehicle. The big cars rule! To complete the specification of the victimization probabilities, we assume that if (s, t) = (0, 0), the probabilities are both 1/2. We will assume that party X knows her vehicle size s, and that party Y knows her vehicle size t. We will assume that both know the equations determining the true victimization probabilities. However, X may or may not know Y s vehicle size, and vice versa. If each party knows the other s vehicle size, then the subjective probabilities must equal the true probabilities. Otherwise, the subjective probabilities may differ from the true probabilities. In Sections below, we will assume that the parties do know the other person s vehicle size, and so the subjective probabilities are also true probabilities. In Section 3.5, we will assume that the parties may not know the other person s vehicle size Incorporating vehicle size in the decision process As a first simple case, assume that X and Y have fixed, pre-determined vehicle sizes, that the sizes s and t are known to both, and that they are choosing care levels x and y, subject to one of the negligence-based rules analyzed above. Since X and Y know both vehicle sizes, α = ᾱ and β = β, and therefore α + β = 1. Therefore, under Results 3 5 above, no matter which standard negligence-based rule is in effect, the unique Nash equilibrium care levels are at (x *, y * ).

15 J. Kim, A.M. Feldman / International Review of Law and Economics 26 (2006) When (x *, y * ) is the Nash equilibrium for the care levels, both parties are taking adequate care, and therefore under all the standard negligence-based rules, all of the accident losses fall on the victim. We conclude, therefore, party X s expected cost is: C X = x + t s + t p(x,y )L (12) Next, we continue to assume that the sizes s and t are known to both. But now we allow party X to adjust her vehicle size s, while taking party Y s vehicle size t as given. We let r represent the cost per unit of vehicle size, so that a vehicle of size s costs rs. By the arguments in Section 2 above, any Nash equilibrium requires that the care levels be at the efficient (x *, y * ). Anticipating a Nash equilibrium in the care levels at (x *, y * ), and deciding what sized vehicle to choose, party X wants to choose s to minimize C X + rs = x + t s + t p(x,y )L + rs The first order condition for a minimum leads easily to s = ( t r p(x,y )L) 1/2 t (13) 3.2. Nash equilibrium in vehicle size We are continuing to assume that the sizes s and t are visible to both. But now we assume that both parties, X and Y, are minimizing expected private costs plus vehicle size costs, each taking the other s (optimal) care as a given, and each taking the other s vehicle size as a given. We wish to find a Nash equilibrium in vehicle sizes (which lies on top of the Nash equilibrium in care levels). Party X is solving Eq. (13), and party Y is solving an analogous equation. It is then easy to show that the resulting vehicle size choices, s *, t *, are given by 15 s = t = 1 4r p(x,y )L (14) Total expenditure on vehicle size is of course a pure social waste in this model, since it has no function other than to throw fixed damages on the other party in the event of an accident. We will call this social cost vehicle size waste, and abbreviate it VSW; it is of course an addition to the previously defined TSC, which only comprises care costs plus expected accident costs. The vehicle size waste is trivially derived from equation (14) above, as follows: VSW = rs + rt = 1 2 p(x,y )L (15) 15 Note that we are using the * notation in a different sense for vehicle sizes than for care levels. For care levels, a * designates a total-social-cost-minimizing level of care for a party, which she might (or might not) choose. For vehicle sizes, a * designates a chosen size, which normally will not be total-social-cost-minimizing, since the social-cost-minimizing sizes in the model will both be zero.

Victim or Injurer: Negligence-Based Liability Rules Under Role-Type Uncertainty, With An Extension to Collisions Of Different-Sized Vehicles

Victim or Injurer: Negligence-Based Liability Rules Under Role-Type Uncertainty, With An Extension to Collisions Of Different-Sized Vehicles Victim or Injurer: Negligence-Based Liability Rules Under Role-Type Uncertainty, With An Etension to Collisions Of Different-Sized Vehicles Jeonghyun Kim and Allan M. Feldman Working Paper No. 2003-17

More information

1. Introduction. (1989), Mark (1994), Burrow (1999), and Wright (2002)

1. Introduction. (1989), Mark (1994), Burrow (1999), and Wright (2002) 1. Introduction This paper has two main objectives. The first objective is to contribute to an important and current debate. This debate is regarding the desirability as well as the implications of the

More information

Comparative Vigilance: A Simple Guide. September 3, 2008 Abstract

Comparative Vigilance: A Simple Guide. September 3, 2008 Abstract Comparative Vigilance: A Simple Guide Brown University Department of Economics Working Paper No. 2008-11 Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics, Brown University Providence, RI 02906 USA Allan_Feldman@Brown.edu

More information

Chapter 2 An Economic Model of Tort Law

Chapter 2 An Economic Model of Tort Law Chapter 2 An Economic Model of Tort Law 2.1. The Basic Accident Model Unilateral Care Model. Suppose first that only the injurer can take care. Let x = the dollar expenditure on care by the injurer; L(x)

More information

A Neglected Interdependency in Liability Theory

A Neglected Interdependency in Liability Theory A Neglected Interdependency in Liability Theory Dhammika Dharmapala, Sandy Hoffmann, Warren Schwartz July 2001 Discussion Paper 01 13 Resources for the Future 1616 P Street, NW Washington, D.C. 20036 Telephone:

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE SOCIAL VERSUS THE PRIVATE INCENTIVE TO BRING SUIT IN A COSTLY LEGAL SYSTEM. Steven Shavell. Working Paper No.

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE SOCIAL VERSUS THE PRIVATE INCENTIVE TO BRING SUIT IN A COSTLY LEGAL SYSTEM. Steven Shavell. Working Paper No. NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE SOCIAL VERSUS THE PRIVATE INCENTIVE TO BRING SUIT IN A COSTLY LEGAL SYSTEM Steven Shavell Working Paper No. T4l NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue

More information

Chapter 7 Topics in the Economics of Tort Liability

Chapter 7 Topics in the Economics of Tort Liability Chapter 7 Topics in the Economics of Tort Liability I. Extending the Economic Model A. Relaxing the core assumptions of the model developed in the previous chapter 1. Decision makers are rational In order

More information

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants

Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants Impact of Imperfect Information on the Optimal Exercise Strategy for Warrants April 2008 Abstract In this paper, we determine the optimal exercise strategy for corporate warrants if investors suffer from

More information

Liability Situations with Joint Tortfeasors

Liability Situations with Joint Tortfeasors Liability Situations with Joint Tortfeasors Frank Huettner European School of Management and Technology, frank.huettner@esmt.org, Dominik Karos School of Business and Economics, Maastricht University,

More information

Compensating for Unforeseeable Damages in Torts

Compensating for Unforeseeable Damages in Torts Compensating for Unforeseeable Damages in Torts Jeong-Yoo Kim Kyung Hee University November 6, 2007 Abstract The doctrine regarding unforeseeable damages in a contract was established in the well known

More information

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation

Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation Journal of Economics and Finance Volume 24 Number 1 Spring 2000 Pages 56-63 Revenue Equivalence and Income Taxation Veronika Grimm and Ulrich Schmidt* Abstract This paper considers the classical independent

More information

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies

Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Chapter 5 Regret Minimization and Security Strategies Until now we implicitly adopted a view that a Nash equilibrium is a desirable outcome of a strategic game. In this chapter we consider two alternative

More information

Chapter 6 An Economic Theory of Tort Law

Chapter 6 An Economic Theory of Tort Law Chapter 6 An Economic Theory of Tort Law I. Defining Tort Law A. Intentional versus unintentional torts An intentional tort is one in which the defendant intended to cause harm to the plaintiff by an act

More information

Settlement and the Strict Liability-Negligence Comparison

Settlement and the Strict Liability-Negligence Comparison Settlement and the Strict Liability-Negligence Comparison Abraham L. Wickelgren UniversityofTexasatAustinSchoolofLaw Abstract Because injurers typically have better information about their level of care

More information

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University \ins\liab\liabinfo.v3d 12-05-08 Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain Information About Risk Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas December

More information

Lecture 4. Introduction to the economics of tort law

Lecture 4. Introduction to the economics of tort law Lecture 4. Introduction to the economics of tort law Lecture outline What are torts? The elements of an actionable tort Different liability rules Properties of different liability rules Errors Risk aversion

More information

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments

Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments Auctions That Implement Efficient Investments Kentaro Tomoeda October 31, 215 Abstract This article analyzes the implementability of efficient investments for two commonly used mechanisms in single-item

More information

Mistakes, Negligence and Liabilty. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University. Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas.

Mistakes, Negligence and Liabilty. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University. Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas. \ins\liab\mistakes.v1a 11-03-09 Mistakes, Negligence and Liabilty Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas November, 2009 Thistle would like to thank Lorne

More information

Partial privatization as a source of trade gains

Partial privatization as a source of trade gains Partial privatization as a source of trade gains Kenji Fujiwara School of Economics, Kwansei Gakuin University April 12, 2008 Abstract A model of mixed oligopoly is constructed in which a Home public firm

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren October, 2013 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

The Welfare Implications of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability

The Welfare Implications of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability Berkeley Law Berkeley Law Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1988 The Welfare Implications of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability A. Mitchell Polsinky Daniel L. Rubinfeld Berkeley

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS. Steven Shavell. Working Paper

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS. Steven Shavell. Working Paper NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS Steven Shavell Working Paper 11781 http://www.nber.org/papers/w11781 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge, MA 02138

More information

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence

Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence Appendix: Common Currencies vs. Monetary Independence A The infinite horizon model This section defines the equilibrium of the infinity horizon model described in Section III of the paper and characterizes

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV GAME THEORY SOLUTION SET 1 WINTER 018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction For suggested solution to problem 4, last year s suggested solutions by Tsz-Ning Wong were used who I think used suggested

More information

Economic Arguments For Comparative Negligence and The Reasonable Person Standard

Economic Arguments For Comparative Negligence and The Reasonable Person Standard Economic Arguments For Comparative Negligence and The Reasonable Person Standard Seb Moosapoor November 6, 2012 Abstract Rules that apportion monetary damages between tort litigants affect the precautionary

More information

Definition of Incomplete Contracts

Definition of Incomplete Contracts Definition of Incomplete Contracts Susheng Wang 1 2 nd edition 2 July 2016 This note defines incomplete contracts and explains simple contracts. Although widely used in practice, incomplete contracts have

More information

THE EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE CAUSATION

THE EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE CAUSATION CDE June 2009 THE EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE CAUSATION Francesco Parisi Email: parisi@umn.edu University of Minnesota and University of Bologna Department of Economics Ram Singh Email: ramsingh@econdse.org

More information

Characterization of the Optimum

Characterization of the Optimum ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 5. Portfolio Allocation with One Riskless, One Risky Asset Characterization of the Optimum Consider a risk-averse, expected-utility-maximizing

More information

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to

PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV. If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to GAME THEORY PROBLEM SET 1 WINTER 2018 PAULI MURTO, ANDREY ZHUKOV Introduction If any mistakes or typos are spotted, kindly communicate them to andrey.zhukov@aalto.fi. Materials from Osborne and Rubinstein

More information

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE

MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE MA300.2 Game Theory 2005, LSE Answers to Problem Set 2 [1] (a) This is standard (we have even done it in class). The one-shot Cournot outputs can be computed to be A/3, while the payoff to each firm can

More information

On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation

On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation May 1, 1997 On the 'Lock-In' Effects of Capital Gains Taxation Yoshitsugu Kanemoto 1 Faculty of Economics, University of Tokyo 7-3-1 Hongo, Bunkyo-ku, Tokyo 113 Japan Abstract The most important drawback

More information

Problem Set 2 Answers

Problem Set 2 Answers Problem Set 2 Answers BPH8- February, 27. Note that the unique Nash Equilibrium of the simultaneous Bertrand duopoly model with a continuous price space has each rm playing a wealy dominated strategy.

More information

Information and Evidence in Bargaining

Information and Evidence in Bargaining Information and Evidence in Bargaining Péter Eső Department of Economics, University of Oxford peter.eso@economics.ox.ac.uk Chris Wallace Department of Economics, University of Leicester cw255@leicester.ac.uk

More information

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions

Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions Microeconomic Theory II Preliminary Examination Solutions 1. (45 points) Consider the following normal form game played by Bruce and Sheila: L Sheila R T 1, 0 3, 3 Bruce M 1, x 0, 0 B 0, 0 4, 1 (a) Suppose

More information

On the Judgment Proof Problem

On the Judgment Proof Problem The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 27: 143 152, 2002 c 2003 The Geneva Association On the Judgment Proof Problem RICHARD MACMINN Illinois State University, College of Business, Normal, IL

More information

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12

CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 CUR 412: Game Theory and its Applications, Lecture 12 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO May 24, 2016 Announcements Homework #4 is due next week. Review of Last Lecture In extensive games with imperfect information,

More information

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours

Aggregation with a double non-convex labor supply decision: indivisible private- and public-sector hours Ekonomia nr 47/2016 123 Ekonomia. Rynek, gospodarka, społeczeństwo 47(2016), s. 123 133 DOI: 10.17451/eko/47/2016/233 ISSN: 0137-3056 www.ekonomia.wne.uw.edu.pl Aggregation with a double non-convex labor

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2017 These notes have been used and commented on before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please

More information

Will No-Fault Insurance Cost More Or Less?

Will No-Fault Insurance Cost More Or Less? Catholic University Law Review Volume 21 Issue 2 Winter 1972 Article 13 1972 Will No-Fault Insurance Cost More Or Less? C. Arthur Williams Jr. Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.edu/lawreview

More information

Liquidity saving mechanisms

Liquidity saving mechanisms Liquidity saving mechanisms Antoine Martin and James McAndrews Federal Reserve Bank of New York September 2006 Abstract We study the incentives of participants in a real-time gross settlement with and

More information

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion

Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion Two-Dimensional Bayesian Persuasion Davit Khantadze September 30, 017 Abstract We are interested in optimal signals for the sender when the decision maker (receiver) has to make two separate decisions.

More information

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games

Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games CPSC 532l Lecture 10 Stochastic Games and Bayesian Games CPSC 532l Lecture 10, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Stochastic Games 3 Bayesian Games 4 Analyzing Bayesian

More information

Marginal Deterrence When Offenders Act Sequentially

Marginal Deterrence When Offenders Act Sequentially Marginal Deterrence When Offenders Act Sequentially Tim Friehe University of Bonn Thomas J. Miceli University of Connecticut Working Paper 204-09 May 204 365 Fairfield Way, Unit 063 Storrs, CT 06269-063

More information

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing

Online Appendix. Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Online Appendix for Bankruptcy Law and Bank Financing Giacomo Rodano Bank of Italy Nicolas Serrano-Velarde Bocconi University December 23, 2014 Emanuele Tarantino University of Mannheim 1 1 Reorganization,

More information

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium

1 Appendix A: Definition of equilibrium Online Appendix to Partnerships versus Corporations: Moral Hazard, Sorting and Ownership Structure Ayca Kaya and Galina Vereshchagina Appendix A formally defines an equilibrium in our model, Appendix B

More information

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited

Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Comparing Allocations under Asymmetric Information: Coase Theorem Revisited Shingo Ishiguro Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka 560-0043, Japan August 2002

More information

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments 6.1: Introduction This chapter and the next contain almost identical analyses concerning the supply and demand implied by different kinds

More information

Lecture Note 23 Adverse Selection, Risk Aversion and Insurance Markets

Lecture Note 23 Adverse Selection, Risk Aversion and Insurance Markets Lecture Note 23 Adverse Selection, Risk Aversion and Insurance Markets David Autor, MIT and NBER 1 Insurance market unraveling: An empirical example The 1998 paper by Cutler and Reber, Paying for Health

More information

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion?

Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion? Does Retailer Power Lead to Exclusion? Patrick Rey and Michael D. Whinston 1 Introduction In a recent paper, Marx and Shaffer (2007) study a model of vertical contracting between a manufacturer and two

More information

Lecture Notes 6 Economics of the Environment and Natural Resources/Economics of Sustainability K Foster, CCNY, Spring 2011

Lecture Notes 6 Economics of the Environment and Natural Resources/Economics of Sustainability K Foster, CCNY, Spring 2011 Lecture Notes 6 Economics of the Environment and Natural Resources/Economics of Sustainability K Foster, CCNY, Spring 2011 Tradable Permits, continued Can easily show the financial burden on firms. Consider

More information

Mistakes to Avoid If You Are in a Georgia Car Wreck

Mistakes to Avoid If You Are in a Georgia Car Wreck Mistakes to Avoid If You Are in a Georgia Car Wreck JAMES K. MURPHY Murphy Law Firm, LLC Georgia Accident & Injury Attorney 8302 Office Park Drive 2 Table of Contents: Preface: Who is Behind This Book,

More information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information

DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21. Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02. Topic 5: Information Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02 Topic 5: Information Economics 21, Summer 2002 Andreas Bentz Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer 02 Introduction

More information

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty

Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty Efficiency in Decentralized Markets with Aggregate Uncertainty Braz Camargo Dino Gerardi Lucas Maestri December 2015 Abstract We study efficiency in decentralized markets with aggregate uncertainty and

More information

Price Theory of Two-Sided Markets

Price Theory of Two-Sided Markets The E. Glen Weyl Department of Economics Princeton University Fundação Getulio Vargas August 3, 2007 Definition of a two-sided market 1 Two groups of consumers 2 Value from connecting (proportional to

More information

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE

MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE MA200.2 Game Theory II, LSE Problem Set 1 These questions will go over basic game-theoretic concepts and some applications. homework is due during class on week 4. This [1] In this problem (see Fudenberg-Tirole

More information

Chapter 3. Dynamic discrete games and auctions: an introduction

Chapter 3. Dynamic discrete games and auctions: an introduction Chapter 3. Dynamic discrete games and auctions: an introduction Joan Llull Structural Micro. IDEA PhD Program I. Dynamic Discrete Games with Imperfect Information A. Motivating example: firm entry and

More information

Should Victims of Exposure to a Toxic Substance Have an Independent Claim for Medical Monitoring?

Should Victims of Exposure to a Toxic Substance Have an Independent Claim for Medical Monitoring? University of Connecticut DigitalCommons@UConn Economics Working Papers Department of Economics January 2002 Should Victims of Exposure to a Toxic Substance Have an Independent Claim for Medical Monitoring?

More information

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let

April 29, X ( ) for all. Using to denote a true type and areport,let April 29, 2015 "A Characterization of Efficient, Bayesian Incentive Compatible Mechanisms," by S. R. Williams. Economic Theory 14, 155-180 (1999). AcommonresultinBayesianmechanismdesignshowsthatexpostefficiency

More information

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations 19.1: Introduction This chapter is interesting and important. It also helps to answer a question you may well have been asking ever since we studied quasi-linear

More information

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1

Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Leonardo Felli 7 January, 2002 Topics in Contract Theory Lecture 1 Contract Theory has become only recently a subfield of Economics. As the name suggest the main object of the analysis is a contract. Therefore

More information

Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A.

Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A. THE INVISIBLE HAND OF PIRACY: AN ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF THE INFORMATION-GOODS SUPPLY CHAIN Antino Kim Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington Bloomington, IN 47405, U.S.A. {antino@iu.edu}

More information

Social Optimality in the Two-Party Case

Social Optimality in the Two-Party Case Web App p.1 Web Appendix for Daughety and Reinganum, Markets, Torts and Social Inefficiency The Rand Journal of Economics, 37(2), Summer 2006, pp. 300-23. ***** Please note the following two typos in the

More information

ECON Micro Foundations

ECON Micro Foundations ECON 302 - Micro Foundations Michael Bar September 13, 2016 Contents 1 Consumer s Choice 2 1.1 Preferences.................................... 2 1.2 Budget Constraint................................ 3

More information

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems

Microeconomics II. CIDE, MsC Economics. List of Problems Microeconomics II CIDE, MsC Economics List of Problems 1. There are three people, Amy (A), Bart (B) and Chris (C): A and B have hats. These three people are arranged in a room so that B can see everything

More information

Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction. By: Stephen P. Holland

Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction. By: Stephen P. Holland Extraction capacity and the optimal order of extraction By: Stephen P. Holland Holland, Stephen P. (2003) Extraction Capacity and the Optimal Order of Extraction, Journal of Environmental Economics and

More information

Optimal Actuarial Fairness in Pension Systems

Optimal Actuarial Fairness in Pension Systems Optimal Actuarial Fairness in Pension Systems a Note by John Hassler * and Assar Lindbeck * Institute for International Economic Studies This revision: April 2, 1996 Preliminary Abstract A rationale for

More information

Ex Post Liability for Harm vs. Ex Ante Safety Regulation: Substitutes or Complements?

Ex Post Liability for Harm vs. Ex Ante Safety Regulation: Substitutes or Complements? Ex Post Liability for Harm vs. Ex Ante Safety Regulation: Substitutes or Complements? Charles D. Kolstad, Thomas S. Ulen, Gary V. Johnson The American Economic Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (Sep., 1990), pp.

More information

January 26,

January 26, January 26, 2015 Exercise 9 7.c.1, 7.d.1, 7.d.2, 8.b.1, 8.b.2, 8.b.3, 8.b.4,8.b.5, 8.d.1, 8.d.2 Example 10 There are two divisions of a firm (1 and 2) that would benefit from a research project conducted

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 2012 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India October 22 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY Correlated Strategies and Correlated

More information

Theory on the combination of tort law, regulation and pigouvian taxation in a two actor model

Theory on the combination of tort law, regulation and pigouvian taxation in a two actor model Theory on the combination of tort law, regulation and pigouvian taxation in a two actor model Analysis of the best use of policy instruments in combination in a two actor model with limited liability.

More information

Other Regarding Preferences

Other Regarding Preferences Other Regarding Preferences Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Spring 015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University 1 Lecture 1 We are now going to introduce two models of other regarding preferences, and think

More information

Optimal Negligence Rules When Costs of Care Differ

Optimal Negligence Rules When Costs of Care Differ Optimal Negligence Rules When Costs of Care Differ Dagobert L Brito and Peter R. Hartley Rice University There has been considerable controversy about the efficiency of tort liability negligence rules.

More information

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay

Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Sequential Investment, Hold-up, and Strategic Delay Juyan Zhang and Yi Zhang February 20, 2011 Abstract We investigate hold-up in the case of both simultaneous and sequential investment. We show that if

More information

Random Variables and Applications OPRE 6301

Random Variables and Applications OPRE 6301 Random Variables and Applications OPRE 6301 Random Variables... As noted earlier, variability is omnipresent in the business world. To model variability probabilistically, we need the concept of a random

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 5 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 23, 2015 Administrative Stuff Homework 2 is due next week. Due to the change in material covered, I have decided to change the grading system

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program August 2017 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Exercises. (b) Show that x* is increasing in D and decreasing in c. (c) Calculate x* for D=500 and c=10.

Exercises. (b) Show that x* is increasing in D and decreasing in c. (c) Calculate x* for D=500 and c=10. Exercises 1. Consider a unilateral care accident model in which the probability of an accident is given by p(x)=e x, where x is the level of injurer care, and e is the base of the natural logarithm. Let

More information

Supplement to the lecture on the Diamond-Dybvig model

Supplement to the lecture on the Diamond-Dybvig model ECON 4335 Economics of Banking, Fall 2016 Jacopo Bizzotto 1 Supplement to the lecture on the Diamond-Dybvig model The model in Diamond and Dybvig (1983) incorporates important features of the real world:

More information

Education Finance and Imperfections in Information

Education Finance and Imperfections in Information The Economic and Social Review, Vol. 15, No. 1, October 1983, pp. 25-33 Education Finance and Imperfections in Information PAUL GROUT* University of Birmingham Abstract: The paper introduces a model of

More information

License and Entry Decisions for a Firm with a Cost Advantage in an International Duopoly under Convex Cost Functions

License and Entry Decisions for a Firm with a Cost Advantage in an International Duopoly under Convex Cost Functions Journal of Economics and Management, 2018, Vol. 14, No. 1, 1-31 License and Entry Decisions for a Firm with a Cost Advantage in an International Duopoly under Convex Cost Functions Masahiko Hattori Faculty

More information

Economics and Computation

Economics and Computation Economics and Computation ECON 425/563 and CPSC 455/555 Professor Dirk Bergemann and Professor Joan Feigenbaum Reputation Systems In case of any questions and/or remarks on these lecture notes, please

More information

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions?

March 30, Why do economists (and increasingly, engineers and computer scientists) study auctions? March 3, 215 Steven A. Matthews, A Technical Primer on Auction Theory I: Independent Private Values, Northwestern University CMSEMS Discussion Paper No. 196, May, 1995. This paper is posted on the course

More information

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec pp. ec1 ec5

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi /mnsc ec pp. ec1 ec5 MANAGEMENT SCIENCE doi 10.1287/mnsc.1060.0648ec pp. ec1 ec5 e-companion ONLY AVAILABLE IN ELECTRONIC FORM informs 2007 INFORMS Electronic Companion When Do Employees Become Entrepreneurs? by Thomas Hellmann,

More information

Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part 1

Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part 1 Product Di erentiation: Exercises Part Sotiris Georganas Royal Holloway University of London January 00 Problem Consider Hotelling s linear city with endogenous prices and exogenous and locations. Suppose,

More information

What is it. w The economic theory of tort law emphasizes precaution against these risks, deterrence.

What is it. w The economic theory of tort law emphasizes precaution against these risks, deterrence. What is it w Tort law is concerned with accidental injuries. Its purposes are twofold: to compensate victims and to deter unreasonably dangerous behavior, accidents (product liability, medical malpractice,

More information

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1

A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model. of Inequity Aversion 1 A Preference Foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s Model of Inequity Aversion 1 Kirsten I.M. Rohde 2 January 12, 2009 1 The author would like to thank Itzhak Gilboa, Ingrid M.T. Rohde, Klaus M. Schmidt, and

More information

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Chapter 33: Public Goods Chapter 33: Public Goods 33.1: Introduction Some people regard the message of this chapter that there are problems with the private provision of public goods as surprising or depressing. But the message

More information

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly

Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercises Solutions: Oligopoly Exercise - Quantity competition 1 Take firm 1 s perspective Total revenue is R(q 1 = (4 q 1 q q 1 and, hence, marginal revenue is MR 1 (q 1 = 4 q 1 q Marginal cost is MC

More information

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems

Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Online Appendix for Military Mobilization and Commitment Problems Ahmer Tarar Department of Political Science Texas A&M University 4348 TAMU College Station, TX 77843-4348 email: ahmertarar@pols.tamu.edu

More information

Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons

Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons Andrew McLennan September 4, 2014 I. Introduction Economics 6030/8030 Microeconomics B Second Semester 2014 Lecture 6 Adverse Selection: The Market for Lemons A. One of the most famous and influential

More information

Chapter 4. Determination of Income and Employment 4.1 AGGREGATE DEMAND AND ITS COMPONENTS

Chapter 4. Determination of Income and Employment 4.1 AGGREGATE DEMAND AND ITS COMPONENTS Determination of Income and Employment Chapter 4 We have so far talked about the national income, price level, rate of interest etc. in an ad hoc manner without investigating the forces that govern their

More information

NEW YORK STATE BAR ASSOCIATION. LEGALEase. If You Have An Auto Accident

NEW YORK STATE BAR ASSOCIATION. LEGALEase. If You Have An Auto Accident NEW YORK STATE BAR ASSOCIATION LEGALEase If You Have An Auto Accident If You Have An Auto Accident What should you do if you re involved in an automobile accident in New York? STOP! By law, you are required

More information

A Decentralized Learning Equilibrium

A Decentralized Learning Equilibrium Paper to be presented at the DRUID Society Conference 2014, CBS, Copenhagen, June 16-18 A Decentralized Learning Equilibrium Andreas Blume University of Arizona Economics ablume@email.arizona.edu April

More information

The Economic Structure of Tort Law: Market-based or Command and Control? Tze-Shiou Chien

The Economic Structure of Tort Law: Market-based or Command and Control? Tze-Shiou Chien The Economic Structure of Tort Law: Market-based or Command and Control? Tze-Shiou Chien I. Tort law is a branch of private law. The function of private law is to facilitate market transactions. Only in

More information

Bargaining Order and Delays in Multilateral Bargaining with Asymmetric Sellers

Bargaining Order and Delays in Multilateral Bargaining with Asymmetric Sellers WP-2013-015 Bargaining Order and Delays in Multilateral Bargaining with Asymmetric Sellers Amit Kumar Maurya and Shubhro Sarkar Indira Gandhi Institute of Development Research, Mumbai August 2013 http://www.igidr.ac.in/pdf/publication/wp-2013-015.pdf

More information

Government spending in a model where debt effects output gap

Government spending in a model where debt effects output gap MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Government spending in a model where debt effects output gap Peter N Bell University of Victoria 12. April 2012 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/38347/ MPRA Paper

More information

Proof. Suppose the landlord offers the tenant contract P. The highest price the occupant will be willing to pay is p 0 minus all costs relating to

Proof. Suppose the landlord offers the tenant contract P. The highest price the occupant will be willing to pay is p 0 minus all costs relating to APPENDIX A. CONTRACT THEORY MODEL In this section, removed from the manuscript at the request of the reviewers, we develop a stylized model to formalize why split incentives in the owner-occupant relationship

More information

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome.

AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED. November Preliminary, comments welcome. AUCTIONEER ESTIMATES AND CREDULOUS BUYERS REVISITED Alex Gershkov and Flavio Toxvaerd November 2004. Preliminary, comments welcome. Abstract. This paper revisits recent empirical research on buyer credulity

More information

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models

Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models IEOR E4707: Foundations of Financial Engineering c 206 by Martin Haugh Martingale Pricing Theory in Discrete-Time and Discrete-Space Models These notes develop the theory of martingale pricing in a discrete-time,

More information

Trading Company and Indirect Exports

Trading Company and Indirect Exports Trading Company and Indirect Exports Kiyoshi Matsubara June 015 Abstract This article develops an oligopoly model of trade intermediation. In the model, manufacturing firm(s) wanting to export their products

More information