Theories of Tort Law

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Theories of Tort Law"

Transcription

1 Theories of Tort Law A tort is a legal wrong. Tort law is a branch of the civil law; the other main branches are contract and property law. Whereas in criminal law the plaintiff is always the state and the defendant, if found guilty of a crime, is punished by the state, in civil law the dispute is typically between private parties (though the government can also sue and be sued). In the case of torts, the plaintiff is the victim of an alleged wrong and the unsuccessful defendant is either directed by the court to pay damages to the plaintiff (the usual remedy) or else to desist from the wrongful activity (so-called "injunctive relief"). Examples include intentional torts such as battery, defamation, and invasion of privacy and unintentional torts such as negligence. Most contemporary tort theory focuses on the legal consequences of accidents, where the relevant forms of liability are negligence and strict liability. This entry likewise focuses on these forms of liability. Misfortune happens and when it does its victims incur costs. Those costs can remain the burden of victims or they can be shifted to others. Sometimes the costs are borne by everyone (within a particular group or political community). Still other times those costs are borne by particular individuals, namely, those who are responsible for having caused them. The question is: Who is to bear the costs of life's misfortunes: victims, the community as a whole, those who are responsible for them, or someone else entirely? How are we to answer this question? What principles ought to guide the decision, and what institutions ought we create to realize these principles in practice? 1. Introduction 2. The Difference Between Fault and Strict Liability 3. Framework for a Theory of Tort Law 4. Theories of Torts: Economic Analysis 5. Theories of Torts: Corrective Justice Bibliography Other Internet Resources Related Entries 1. Introduction

2 Let's set aside for the moment the costs of misfortune that are borne collectively and distributed throughout the community through tax systems that support, for example, social welfare and safety net programs more generally. Of those that remain, the question is whether the costs are to be borne by victims or some other particular person or persons. Tort law is one of the institutions political communities develop in order to allow victims the opportunity to shift the costs that befall them to others. Insurance is another such institution. Many individuals purchase first party insurance to protect themselves against having to shoulder the full costs of some misfortunes that may befall them and to guard against others. Private health insurance provides a good example of first party insurance against risk to oneself. The contrast is with third party insurance a contract into which one enters to guard against shouldering the full costs of misfortune one imposes on others for which one is held by law to be responsible. Tort law and insurance are connected in the following way. Tort law establishes conditions under which victims can shift at least some of the costs they incur to others. All individuals realize that they may be subject to a judgment against them in torts and so many buy third party insurance to protect them from bearing the full costs of those judgments. In some jurisdictions purchasing third party insurance is mandatory. All individuals are likewise aware that they may be victims of another's actions and may not be able to secure a favorable judgment against their injurers or they not deem it worth the effort to pursue redress through the courts. So many of them buy first party insurance to guard against some of the costs they would otherwise have to shoulder completely. It is important to note that tort law provides an avenue of redress, not a guarantee of recovery. The victim must determine whether pursuing a remedy through torts is worth the effort and cost. Indeed, as an empirical matter most simply grin and bear the loss then move on. When a victim chooses the form of redress provided by tort law she is given the opportunity to shift her losses to another provided the conditions the law sets out for doing so have been met. The conditions for shifting losses from victim-plaintiffs to injurer-defendants are expressed in liability rules. The law of torts distinguishes between two basic kinds of rules: those that impose fault liability and those that impose strict liability. In the next section we will characterize the difference between these liability rules precisely, but for now it may be helpful to illustrate the underlying distinction in familiar terms that do not rely on the technicalities of the law.

3 Suppose I made a mess of some sort on my property, then I turned to you and presented you with the bill for cleaning it up. In the absence of some prior agreement we might have made this would seem rather odd. After all, it is my mess, not yours. The burden, accordingly, is mine, not yours, to discharge. Now suppose that instead of making a mess on my property and presenting you with the bill, I simply move the mess I made to your property (or I make the mess on your property from the get-go), and simply walk away claiming the cleanup problem is now yours. If it was inappropriate of me to present you with the bill for the mess I made on my property, it hardly seems that I have improved matters by placing my mess on your property instead. It is, after all, my mess, and the responsibility of cleaning it up is mine. This is the underlying thought behind strict liability. One has a duty to clean up one's messes, and that responsibility does not appear to depend on how hard one has tried not to make a mess in the first place. On the other hand, unless each of us stays in his respective dwelling, we are bound to make the occasional mess in each other's lives. You would not be justified in demanding of me that I never bump into you or make something of a mess in your life, nor would I be justified in making similar demands of you. What I can demand of you is that you take my interests into account and moderate your behavior accordingly. You need to take reasonable precautions not to harm me; you need to avoid being reckless with respect to my interests. And I am obligated to treat you similarly. That is, what we have a right to demand of one another is that we behave responsibly with respect to the other's interests. This is the underlying thought behind fault liability. The question is which is the appropriate standard of liability in torts? Most tort theorists believe that we cannot answer that question without first answering another namely, what are the goals or aims of tort law? The conditions of liability in torts justify imposing a duty of repair on those who satisfy them only if (a) the duties so imposed are the ones best suited to help tort law meet its goals, and (b) the goals are themselves justified. The primary focus of tort theory has been to identify the goals of tort law and to justify them as legitimate aims for the law to pursue. Once the goals are identified and justified, tort theory is then a matter of exploring the extent to which the conditions of liability in torts are appropriate instruments for pursuing them. Put this way, tort theory is largely a normative activity that appears to eschew explanatory projects. Whereas explanatory projects in law can be pursued without

4 raising justificatory questions, it is less clear that justificatory projects of this sort can be pursued completely independently of basic explanatory ones. Consider the claim that the goal of tort law is deterrence. The claim is not that deterrence is a legitimate goal for some logically possible tort law. The claim is that deterrence, for example, is the goal of this or that system of tort law; and making out such a claim requires showing that the law makes sense as the sort of thing that could pursue that goal or aim. That requires in turn establishing that various features of existing or idealized practice makes sense in the light of the goal one attributes to it. In that sense, the normative project requires that we address certain explanatory or conceptual questions. And so part of making the case that say, the efficient reduction of accident costs is the goal of tort law rests on showing that fundamental features of actual tort practice are best explained by seeing them in the light of efficiency. As noted above tort law has both strict and fault liability rules. Thus, we have at least two projects. The first project is to distinguish between fault and strict liability as conditions of liability in torts. The second is to explore the extent to which the central features of tort law including the rules of fault and strict liability can be explained by the putative goals of tort law. 2. The Difference between Fault and Strict Liability There are three basic elements in a tort: wrong, harm and an appropriate relationship between the injurer's wrong and the harm to the victim. To harm someone is to set back a legitimate interest of hers. The law does not recognize all harms as grounds for a claim in torts. If you beat me in tennis or in competition for the affections of another, I may be harmed, and you may be the cause of it, but I have no claim in torts to repair for my broken heart or my bruised ego. Even if the interests harmed are protected by the law, claims to repair for the losses one imposes on others require more than risk and harm; they require a wrong the violation of a duty not to harm or not to impose risks of a certain kind on others. You have no duty not to harm me through competition in business or the affections of another, and so in harming me you do not thereby wrong me. There is no overstating the importance of the idea of a wrong or of a breach of duty to tort law. The central idea in tort law is that liability is based not so much on acting badly or wrongfully, but on committing a wrong. At the same time, a victim's claim to

5 recover for harm to her depends on the wrong the injurer has committed being a wrong to her. It is not enough that the injurer has committed a wrong and that she (the victim) has suffered as a consequence. The defendant's liability to the victim and the victim's claim against the defendant depend on the defendant's having breached a duty of care to the victim. Just as harm without wrong is no tort, wrongs without harms are typically not torts either. Suppose for a moment that every motorist has a duty to exercise reasonable care in driving his or her car, and that the intended beneficiaries of the duty include all the pedestrians and other drivers who might be put at risk by one's failure to drive with adequate care. Now imagine two people who drive recklessly and in so doing breach the duty we suppose they have, but that one motorist causes damage whereas the other escapes injuring anyone. By hypothesis, both have breached a duty to those whose security is put at risk, and in doing so both have committed wrongs. Only one driver harms someone as a result of the wrongs he commits and thus only he subjects himself to tort liability. So torts require both wrong and, in most cases, harm. A notable exception to the harm requirement is the case in which injunctive relief is awarded in order to prevent harm that is virtually certain but yet to occur. As a general rule though torts require both wrongs and harms. They require more as well: for liability in torts can be imposed only if the harm has been caused in the appropriate way by the wrong. A's wrong must be what the law calls the proximate cause of B's harm. These are the elements of a tort, but the question is how are they represented in the context of the rules of strict and fault liability. On the conventional view, the difference between fault and strict liability is that in strict liability, but not in fault liability, a defendant can be liable even if he has done nothing wrong. The common understanding, then, is that strict liability is liability without wrong, and fault liability alone is liability based on the injurer's wrong. But then the conventional view seems incompatible with the claim that all torts involve wrongs. There is a distinction between wrongs and wrongdoings a difference between committing a wrong and acting wrongfully. To act wrongfully is to act without justification or excuse. Wrongdoing reflects badly on an agent for his actions. On the other hand, to commit a wrong is to breach a duty, to invade another's right. One can breach a duty for good reason, with adequate justification, or under

6 excusing conditions. Rights in other words can be invaded innocently (or justifiably) on the one hand, or wrongfully (or unjustifiably) on the other. This distinction is sometimes expressed in terms of the difference between rightsinfringements and rights-violations. Whether my action invades your right is one thing; whether, if it does, the action reflects poorly or favorably on me is another. Let's apply this distinction to the conventional understanding of the difference between strict and fault liability. When liability is imposed strictly, the question is whether the defendant has invaded the plaintiff's right. A plaintiff under strict liability does not have to establish the fault of the defendant, though a judgment of strict liability does not necessarily mean that the defendant has acted innocently or justifiably. According to the conventional view, under fault liability, the plaintiff has to establish not only that he was wronged by the defendant but that in doing so the defendant acted wrongfully, that is, without justification or excuse. But this way of explaining the distinction between fault and strict liability leads us even further astray. For if the victim's being wronged by the defendant is adequate to ground his claim to repair (other things being equal) in some cases, why is it not enough in all cases? Concern for the character of the defendant's action may be appropriate to the question whether, in addition to incurring a duty to make his victims whole, he should be punished, held up to ridicule or banished from the community. Under strict liability, the breach of the duty is what is relevant to the duty to repair. In other words, if a practice of strict liability is justified at all, then the duty to make repair cannot depend on whether the injurer has acted justifiably or not. If that is so, why should the duty of repair in fault liability require more than it does in strict liability? When fault is treated as an element of a tort distinct from the breach of duty, either fault liability requires too much or strict liability too little. The conventional understanding of the difference between fault and strict liability goes astray precisely because it distinguishes the breach of the duty from the fault requirement. The better view is that the difference between fault and strict liability is a difference in the content of the underlying duty of care. To see this, consider the cases of blasting, on the one hand, and motoring on the other. In a case like blasting an activity traditionally falling under strict liability the blaster has a duty-not-to-harm-by-blasting. This is the content of the duty of care blasters owe those whom their blasting puts in danger. On the other hand, in the case of motoring a familiar example of an activity covered fault liability the motorist

7 is thought to have a duty-not-to-harm-by-faultily-motoring. That these duties have different content is illustrated by their respective success and failure conditions. A blaster fails to discharge his duty when his blasting, regardless of the care he takes, injures someone to whom he owes the duty. A motorist fails to discharge his duty when he harms another negligently, recklessly or intentionally through his driving. The blaster can satisfy his obligations only by not harming another. The motorist can meet hers either by not harming anyone or, in the event she harms someone, by not having done so negligently, recklessly or intentionally. And this is just another way of saying that the contents of the respective duties differ. The fault requirement is thus an aspect of the underlying duty, not a reflection on the character of the defendant's action. The force the interests of others imposes on our duty to moderate our behavior varies with the circumstances. Sometimes, the likelihood or magnitude of harm to others is so great that the duty we have to others is not to harm them as a result of the actions we choose to undertake. At other times, the balance of interests indicates that we need to take reasonable precautions to guard against harm to others, and no more. Understood in this way, the problem is familiar and not in the least unique to tort law. It is a matter of ordinary morality that the content of our duties to others varies as a consequence of a range of familiar factors. Noting this does not solve the problem of telling us why sometimes the duty is strict and other times it demands only reasonable care. But the difference is that between points on a continuum, and so the stark contrasts that are implied in the conventional view are inapt. 3. Framework for a Theory of Tort Law It is customary in tort theory to distinguish substantive from structural and procedural aspects of tort law. The rules of strict and fault liability are substantive features of tort law. The bilateral structure of a tort suit the fact that victims sue those they identify as their injurers and do not instead seek repair from a common pool of resources (as is the case in New Zealand) is a structural feature of our tort law. The fact that the burden of bringing forward a claim and of making the prima facie case falls to the plaintiff is a procedural feature of tort law, and so on. We have already identified the most basic substantive concern of a tort theory, and that is to justify, insofar as possible, the rules of fault and strict liability. It is not the only substantive feature of the practice that has drawn the attention of theorists, as the following summary of substantive concerns helps to make clear.

8 Mischief, even great mischief, that does not materialize into harm, may be wrongful, but it is not tortuous. Similarly, a reckless and irresponsible defendant who is fortunate to escape causing major damage to others, is only liable for the minor damages he causes. This in stark contrast to the generally focused and attentive actor whose minor mischief occasions a great deal of misfortune. The general principle of tort is that both are liable for the full costs of the harms their conduct has occasioned. Yet, the burdens they face bear no relationship to the degree of their relative wrongdoing. Why should fortuity play so pervasive and powerful a role in tort law? A defendant judged liable in torts incurs a duty to make good the full costs of the harms that result from his wrong. The liability takes the form of the imposition of a duty of repair. The defendant, however, is often able to discharge his duty through an insurance mechanism. The contrast with the criminal law can be illuminating. It is unimaginable that we would permit individuals to purchase insurance against the likelihood of criminal liability. What explains the difference? 4. Theories of Torts: Economic Analysis Competing theories of tort law offer accounts of these various features of tort law. The degree to which they illuminate our practice is relative to their perspective on legal practice It is helpful to understand tort law through the lens of a judge deciding cases based on prior rulings and doctrine, from the perspective of potential litigants seeking the vindication of claims, and from the perspective of the legal reformer trying to formulate the best rules for imposing liability. Economic analysis of law is unconvincing if its aim is to illuminate the law from the perspective of either judge or litigant. It is much more plausible when viewed through the lens of a particular kind of legal reformer. We will get the most from economic analysis if we remind ourselves that the economic analyst is asking questions of the following sort: what substantive liability rules are most likely to have the greatest impact on reducing the incidence of accidents at the lowest cost? What procedural rules at a trial are most likely to induce those with the most relevant information to reveal it, or most likely to lead to optimal investments in information or safety; and so on. These are the questions of a reformer less interested in the actual state of tort law than in how the law can be improved. The economic approach to tort law, like the economic approach to law more generally, attributes a particular goal to the law: namely, efficiency. In the case of

9 tort law, efficiency is understood as optimal cost reduction. The aim of tort law is to minimize the sum of the costs of accidents and the costs of avoiding them. This is to be accomplished in part by creating a system of incentives adequate to induce individuals to invest appropriately in determining what the optimal precautions are and to take them. The distinguishing feature of economic analysis is the account it provides of fault: the formula it offers for determining whether an actor has adequately taken into account the interests of others. In general, to be at fault in torts is to fail to take others interests appropriately into account and to adjust one's conduct accordingly. Reasonable persons take the interests of others appropriately into account and adjust their behavior accordingly. To be at fault is to fail to behave as would a reasonable person of ordinary prudence. It is a failure to accord others the appropriate level of care to guard against harming their interests. Economic analysts focus primarily on the concept of negligence. Negligence is the failure to take adequate care and adequate care consists in taking cost-justified precautions. Precautions are cost-justified whenever their cost is less than the costs of the harm risked (by not taking precautions) discounted by the probability of the harm's occurrence. Once we understand negligence as the failure to take costjustified precautions we need to ask what justifies imposing liability on those who have failed to take appropriate precautions. From an economic point of view, the costs of the accident for which one is responsible are sunk. There is nothing to be done about them. All that we can do is shift the costs from the victim upon whom they have fallen to someone else. From the economic point of view, such a decision must be based on the impact of cost imposition on the incentives of individuals to invest appropriately in safety. Individuals ought to bear sunk costs only if imposing those costs on them will have the desired impact on the reduction of costs in the future. The responsibility relationship is backward looking; the cost reduction aim is forward looking. It may turn out that having the property of being responsible for a harm may be reliably connected to the property of being an effective cost-avoider. Even in that case, being responsible for a loss is not the groundof liability, but is instead a reliable indicator that the injurer possesses the property that is the ground of liability. Beyond that, if having the property of being responsible for a harm is a reliable indicator that one has the property of being a good cost-avoider (even of harms of the particular sort for which one is responsible), it does not follow, without more,

10 that one should be held liable for the particular harm for which one is responsible. One could just as well be held to bear the costs of a similar injury, or one could be held to bear the costs adequate to induce investments in cost reduction and those costs may or may not coincide with the costs associated with the harm for which one is responsible. So it cannot be part of an economic argument that the party who is at fault must pay for the costs of harms that are his fault because he is responsible for them. Rather, liability is imposed on those at fault in order to put in place the right incentives on the defendant and those similarly situated. If we assume that actors are fully rational and informed, imposing liability on those at fault will have the desired effect on others. Here's the argument. If we assume that agents are fully rational, then under the economic conception of rationality it follows that they will maximize benefits or minimize costs. If agents are fully informed, they know the costs of liability and the costs of precautions. Ex ante, all agents will choose the lesser of these costs. The relationship between precaution costs and potential liability based on fault is as follows. An agent will be at fault only if the costs of precautions are less than the costs of the harm discounted by the probability of occurrence. To avoid being at fault the rational agent takes the precautions, which, in addition, are the lesser costs he faces. If the costs of precautions exceed the cost of the harm discounted by the probability of its occurrence, then he will not take precautions, but then he will not be negligent either. Should harm to another result, he will not be required to shoulder the victim's costs. That will be for the victim to do (an important consequence of fault liability to which we shall return below.) So the rational and informed agent will take precautions whenever it would be efficient for him to do so, not otherwise. In contrast to fault, strict liability is imposed whether or not an agent ought to have taken precautions. Why might we want to hold someone liable who has in fact invested in cost-justified precautions? The economic answer to this puzzle in effect is that there is more than one way to skin a cat. Skinning a cat, in this context, amounts to inducing individuals to take cost-justified precautions. An agent subject to strict liability has to bear the full costs of his activities the costs to him of engaging in it and the costs his engaging in it imposes on others. All the costs are his. The question he faces, then, is whether there is anything he might do to reduce the costs he faces. That depends on whether there are precautions he can take, their costs and their expected effectiveness. In other words, if the costs of precautions are less than the harms likely to occur discounted

11 by the probability of their occurrence, then he will take the precautions. He does so because these costs are lower than those he would otherwise expect. Notice that those precautions are in fact the cost justified ones. And so under strict liability the rational and informed agent will also be induced to take all and only cost justified precautions. In this respect fault and strict liability give the same results. The only difference between the two is that under fault liability the costs of accidents not worth preventing are borne by victims, whereas under strict liability, those same costs are borne by injurers. In fault liability, the costs of accidents that are no one's fault are the burden of victims; in strict liability, they are the burden of injurers. If strict liability can induce efficient investments in safety, why would we have a rule of fault liability? If fault liability is capable of inducing individuals to take optimal precautions, why impose strict liability? The two rules have different distributional consequences. From the economic point of view, the distributional consequences are not important in their own right, but they can be important because of their impact on activity levels. The choice of strict or fault liability is in one sense a choice between making activities more or less expensive relative to each other. Take ranching and farming for example. A rule of strict liability imposed on ranchers for the damage their straying cows impose on corn crops makes ranching more expensive relative to farming. This means that even if, at any level of ranching and farming, both strict and fault liability could be efficient in reducing accidents at that level, a rule of strict liability will make ranching relatively more expensive and reduce the overall level of it (in relation to farming). This means more farming and more farming accidents and fewer ranching related accidents. And so on. If efficiency depends on activity levels, then fault and strict liability need not be equally efficient. Or put another way, because fault and strict liability have differential impacts on activity levels, they can be used differentially whenever appropriate to secure an efficient overall allocation of risks. The implications of fault and strict liability are more complicated once we distinguish between one and two party accidents. A one party accident is one in which in order optimally to reduce the probability of its occurrence only one of the parties to the accident need take appropriate precautions. In contrast, in a two party accident, securing the optimal reduction in the probability of the accident's occurrence requires that both parties take appropriate precautions. Setting aside the problem of activity levels, we can be taken to have shown that in the case of one party accidents both strict and fault liability can be efficient. The same is not true in the case of two party accidents, where strict liability is not efficient. In strict

12 liability, the victim is always compensated his full damages and therefore has no incentive to invest in precautions, yet the situation requires him to do so. In contrast, the rule of fault liability is efficient in the two party case in that it induces both injurers and victims to make optimal investments in safety. The rule of fault liability imposes liability on the injurer only if he is at fault. If the injurer is rational, he will always take the cost justified precautions. We established this result above in the discussion of the one party accident case. Thus, the rational injurer will never be at fault. If people are always rational, then the costs of whatever accidents occur will fall to their victims. Victims must assume, then, that the costs of all accidents will be theirs to bear. Notice that this puts the victim in the exact position the injurer is in under strict liability. On the assumption that the injurer will never be at fault, the victim will always be responsible for all of his costs. And just like the injurer in strict liability, the victim must decide which, if any, precautions to take. Whenever precaution costs are lower than the expected costs of the harm victims will opt for them, otherwise not. In precisely the same way that strict liability encourages injurers to take optimal precautions, fault liability encourages the victim to do the same. If fault liability is efficient, so too is strict liability with the defense of plaintiff or contributory negligence. Here is another simple proof. This proof relies on the fact that the rule of fault liability imposed on defendants can be redescribed as the rule that victims are strictly liable for the costs of harms that befall them unless they can establish the fault of their injurer. What we call fault liability can just as easily be characterized as strict liability for victims with the defense of injurer fault. But if this rule is efficient, then so too is the rule of strict (injurer) liability with the defense of victim fault. They are the same rule. All that changes is that every occurrence of victim is replaced with injurer and vice versa. One rule is efficient if and only if the other is. The rule of fault liability is efficient, and therefore the rule of strict liability with plaintiff fault must be as well. In those cases in which both rules are efficient, the choice between the two depends on other features of the rules: in particular, costs associated with their administration. [1] Notwithstanding the fact that it illuminates important features of legal practice and remains an invaluable tool in the assessment and reform of the law, economic analysis has spawned considerable criticism. Let's begin with two straightforward

13 objections. Economic analysis reduces reasonable risk taking to rational risk taking. In doing so, it treats the care I owe you as identical to the care I would owe myself. Suppose I engage in an activity whose benefit to me is 100 and whose costs to me varies. Whenever the costs to me are under 100 it will be rational for me to absorb the costs and continue on. As soon as the costs to me exceed the benefits, it will no longer be rational for me to engage in the activity. Economic analysis draws no distinction between the case in which the costs and benefits are mine alone and the case in which the benefits are mine to enjoy and the costs yours to endure. But what is reasonable to expect of me when all the costs are mine to bear may not be what is reasonable to demand of me when the benefits are mine to enjoy and the costs yours to bear. To be sure, there is no difference between these cases from the point of view of collective rationality, but that is just the point. There is no reason to identify the reasonable with the rational in the torts context, where one party (the injurer) secures the benefits (in the form of freedom from the costs of precautions) and the other party (the victim) bears the costs (in the form of the costs of injuries more likely to occur). Economic analysis in effect imposes the fungability of costs on the practice of torts without showing that in fact the practice treats costs in this way. That is one reason for thinking that economic analysts are reformers, not analysts of tort law. Now the economic arguments we have considered talk loosely of fault and strict liability, but nowhere invoke the notion of a duty. As we have already seen, the duty element of a tort has two dimensions. The first concerns those to whom I owe a duty of care; the second concerns the content of that duty. As we noted above, the fault standard is part of the content of some of our duties to others; it does not mark out the class of individuals to whom I have a duty. The distinction between the scope and content of the duty of care is central to the American tort case, Palsgraf v. Long Island R.R.. Famously, Judge Cardozo argued that each of us has a duty to moderate our actions by taking into account only the interests of those who fall within the ambit of foreseeable risk. I have to guard against injuring those who fall within the zone of danger associated with my conduct. Others may be injured by what I do, and what I do may have been lamentable or mischievous, but those who fall outside the ambit of foreseeable risk have no claim in torts against me. They have no claim, not because I did not act badly or carelessly. Ex hypothesi, I have. They have no claim against me because I did not wrong them. I did not wrong them because I had no duty to take their interests into account in regulating my conduct. This point cannot be emphasized enough. The only

14 individuals who can in torts have a claim against me are those to whom I have a duty of care. It is only with respect to those individuals that I must exercise reasonable care. The problem for economic analysis is that the duty restriction on liability is incompatible with the goal of inducing individuals to take appropriate precautions. In order to encourage injurers to take appropriate precautions, each must face the full costs of his activity. But the duty requirement allows injurers to displace at least some of the costs of their conduct, costs that efficiency requires them to internalize. This is one reason that economic analysis has no place for the duty requirement. Relatedly, tort law imposes the costs associated with the actual causal upshots of an individual's action. From an economic point of view, it is the risk of harm and not actual harm that should matter. One has to be careful not to misunderstand this point. Harms are of interest to the economic analyst. But the harms that matter from an economic point of view are the ones that have not yet occurred the ones that can be optimally avoided by inducing individuals to take proper precautions and not the harm that occasioned the case at hand. If what matters is reducing the incidence of future harms, then the main concern of economic analysis should be conduct that risks harm. Some conduct that risks harm actually causes harm as well, but not all conduct that risks harm does. Harm that has occurred is of interest only insofar as it provides reliable evidence of riskiness of the underlying conduct. In our tort practice, however, harm, not the risk of it, is a ground of liability and not merely an epistemic convenience. To the extent that the fact of harm is central to the practice of tort law and not an artifact of our limited epistemic capacities, the economic analysis falls short. Finally, let us turn to the structure of tort law. Tort law has a bilateral structure. If the victim of another's mischief brings an action in torts, he brings it against the person he alleges has harmed him. In making out his case, the plaintiff argues that the defendant breached a duty of care owed to him, and that the breach has resulted in the harm of which he complains. From the normative point of view, the most basic relationship in torts is that between the injurer and the victim whom he has wronged. From the economic point of view, the most basic relationship is that between each litigant, taken separately, and the goal of minimizing the sum of accident and accident avoidance costs. That is, economic analysis separates the injurer from the victim. The relevant normative questions are: (1) what is the

15 relationship between the injurer's conduct and the goals of tort law (cost reduction), and (2) what is the relationship between the victim's conduct and the goals of tort law? The relationship between particular victims and injurers matters to economic analysis only insofar as features of it might provide evidence of the ability of either to reduce accident costs. Since the aim of accident law is optimally to reduce accident costs, the loss should be imposed on that individual who is in the best position to reduce costs at the lowest cost. This means that from an economic point of view, there is no reason why the victim should be suing the person he alleges injured him. 5. Theories of Torts: Corrective Justice According to the principle of corrective justice, an individual who has wronged another has a duty to repair the wrongful losses occasioned thereby. The corrective justice account thus illuminates not just the bilateral structure of tort litigation, but tort law's emphasis on harm caused rather than harm risked. Arguably, central to tort law is the moral notion of ownership, not the moral notion of blame. Tort law picks out a particular way of recognizing one's ownership of some of the untoward outcomes for which one is responsible. It does this by imposing a duty to make good the costs one's wrongs have imposed on those one has wronged. And so, rather than trying to determine whether the injurer has satisfied the conditions that would warrant blaming him for what he has done, tort law inquires into whether the injurer has satisfied conditions necessary to impose on him a duty to repair the plaintiff's loss. In short, the law asks whether the loss is attributable to him as his doing: whether, to use the currently fashionable phrase, he is outcome responsible for it. In the prevailing view, to be outcome responsible, the outcome must be foreseeable and avoidable. [2] This emphasis on the ascription of responsibility for outcomes rather than on ascriptions of blame or culpability makes sense within the corrective justice account of tort law in ways in which it would not within a traditional retributive view. According to economic analysis, all liabilities are simply one or another cost. There is no significant normative difference among punishments, sanctions, duties of repair and taxes. All that matters is the way in which each impacts rational decision-making. But there are important normative differences among these kinds

16 of costs that this crude picture misses. Tort law imposes a duty of repair, and while it is true that a person who is under a duty to act is constrained in the set of actions open to him, duties are neither punishments nor sanctions. In contrast with tort law, criminal wrongdoers are subject to punishment for their crimes, and while this means that they are not at liberty to prevent others from punishing them, they have no duty to be punished or to permit others to punish them. There are other significant differences between the duty of repair in torts and punishment as a criminal sanction. The duty of repair in torts is a debt of repayment one owes those one has wronged and has injured as a result. Like other debts of repayment, it can be discharged by third parties and not only if the debt holder has authorized repayment. By contrast debts incurred as a result of criminal mischief cannot be discharged by third parties. I cannot serve your prison sentence justly. To be sure, I might be imprisoned for a crime you have committed, and my love for you may lead me to substitute myself for you when the time comes for you to begin your prison term. But both cases involve injustice: the first to me, the second to the world as a whole. Nor can one guard against liability to criminal sanction by purchasing insurance. In contrast, it is common to purchase insurance to guard against the burdens of tort liability. Indeed, in some cases purchasing third party insurance is mandatory. Not only is it a mistake to lump together sanctions, taxes and liability judgments as interchangeable implements in the legal reformer's tool box, the practices for which each is appropriate are governed by different norms. Failure to notice the differences in character of these costs disables one from understanding the underlying norms governing our differing legal and social institutions. The emphasis on duties of repair as well as on the range of ways in which those duties can be discharged consonant with justice is illuminated by the principle of corrective justice in ways in which these features of tort law are not illuminated by either retributive or economic theory. The claim is that corrective justice explains the relationship between the duty to prevent or avoid harm on the one hand, and the duty to repair its costs on the other. It is a principle that grounds duties of repair, not the duties of care that are the bases of those duties of repair. Though it grounds duties of repair, it does not mandate a mechanism by which those duties are to be discharged.

17 It is tempting to think of corrective justice as a goal of tort law in the same way that economists think of efficiency or optimal deterrence as a goal of tort law. The better view is that corrective justice is not a goal of the law in the way in which efficiency might be. Rather, corrective justice itself is a principle of justification; it seeks to articulate grounds upon which a certain category of duties rest. It claims that certain duties of repair or repayment are grounded on one's responsibility for them. The grounds of the duty to repair are: (1) the fact that one has a prior duty to take into account the interests of another and to mitigate one's own conduct accordingly; (2) the fact that one has failed to do so; (3) the fact that one's failure to do so results (in an appropriate way) in harm to another; and (4) the harm that results is one for which can be charged to an agent as his doing, or, in the contemporary jargon, for which he is outcome responsible. No one claims that these grounds must be satisfied if ever an agent is to have a duty of repair or repayment. Corrective justice grounds some, but, very likely, not all of our duties of repair. If this is the way to think about corrective justice, how ought we think about its relationship to fault and strict liability? The question is whether the duties of repair and the conditions under which they arise in tort law are ones which are by and large grounded in the principle of corrective justice so conceived. As I argued above, both strict and fault liability in torts involve wrongs, that is, the breach of an underlying duty of care. The fault in fault liability is not a modifier of the character of the injurer but a constraint on the content of the underlying duty of care he owes the plaintiff. The difference between fault and strict liability standards is a difference in the nature of the content of the underlying duties we owe one another. In strict liability, the defendant is thought to owe the plaintiff a duty of the form A not to harm by X-ing. It is natural to think that the duty is absolute or unconstrained. But it is in fact constrained in several ways, and in each of the ways it is constrained, the duty in strict liability resonates with the conditions of a duty of repair in corrective justice. The blaster is liable strictly, not to everyone who is injured by his conduct, but only to those to whom he owed a duty not to harm by blasting: those who fall within the ambit of foreseeable risk. Second, he is not liable to all those that he injures because he blasts, but only to those that are injured in the appropriate way by his blasting. In strict liability, there are the requirements of a wrong to a plaintiff (class), a harm, the appropriate causal connection between the two, and other elements of responsibility for the outcome, including forseeability and avoidability.

18 These same elements are present in all the classic cases of fault liability. The only difference, as we have noted, above is that in fault liability the content of the underlying duty not to harm differs from the duty in cases of strict liability. In fault, the duty is not to harm faultily, that is, negligently, recklessly or intentionally. In both the duty of repair requires the breach of a duty (a wrong), and responsibility for the outcome (the injury or harm being caused in the appropriate way by that aspect of the conduct that made it a wrong). Arguably, the duties imposed in tort law are paradigmatically duties of corrective justice. The bilateral structure of tort law and the pattern of practical reasoning embodied within it is transparent under the light of corrective justice, while cloudy at best, and mysterious at worst when viewed in the dim light of economic analysis. Moreover, the same principle explains both the structure and substance of tort law, and thus provides explanatory economy as well as consistency. The corrective justice approach to tort law has been the object of serious criticism. I want to focus on three of the most important kinds of these. The first set of objections focuses on the concept of wrong at work in the principle of corrective justice. The second raises questions about the claim that corrective justice is a matter of justice. The third raises broader doubts about the claim that the goal or purpose of tort law is to achieve corrective justice. Let's consider these in turn. As I have characterized it, corrective justice sets out grounds upon which a certain category of duties of repair or repayment are justified. One of the grounds of a duty to repair is the existence of a wrong, that is, the breach of a duty of care to another. One might say that whereas corrective justice theorists have been extremely concerned to specify appropriately the conditions under which it is fair to impose duties to avoid or prevent untoward consequences, they have offered precious little guidance regarding the actual duties to avoid or prevent harm that we owe to one another. This complaint has been expressed in two slightly different forms of criticism. The first is that to the extent that corrective justice offers only an account of what ought to be done when some individuals wrong others and not an account of what constitutes a wrong in the relevant sense, the principle of corrective justice is empty or merely formal. The second is that since the principle of corrective justice appears to leave open what counts as a wrong, it may be that the wrongs that give rise to a duty of repair are merely the failures to take cost justified precautions, in which case the principle of corrective justice collapses into the principle of efficiency. [3] A related objection is that corrective justice offers us no way of determining when a rule of strict liability is appropriately imposed and

19 when a rule of fault liability is. In other words, corrective justice may tell us that strict and fault liability both involve the breach of a duty of care and that the difference between them concerns the content of the relevant duty, but it offers us no guidance as to why some activities call for the duty of care typified by strict liability whereas others call for a duty of care of the sort associated with fault liability. If nothing else, the economic analysis, as we have seen above, gives very clear guidance on this question. In one form or another, the first objection is by far the most pervasive objection to corrective justice accounts of tort law. Were it a sound objection, it would be devastating. In fact, it is not a serious objection, and rests on an important misunderstanding. There is in morality, as elsewhere, a significant, if limited, division of labor. It is not the burden of corrective justice to explain the content of our duties not to harm others or to determine their scope. It is instead a principle that grounds some of the duties we incur in the event that we fail to comply with our duties not to harm others. We have a responsibility in general to mitigate our conduct by the impact it is likely to have on the interests of others. This is a matter of common sense morality and simple fairness. This general duty we have to others is not itself a matter of corrective justice. Nor are the specific duties we have to particular persons to take into account the impact of our conduct on their interests in concrete ways matters of corrective justice. It is a good question of morality, just what it is we owe one another concretely in order to discharge our general obligations of fairness to one another. How must I mitigate my conduct in the light of your (presumably, legitimate) interests? And which of those interests must I take into account? One can hold the view that drawing up a list of such concrete duties is the task of moral philosophy. Others may hold that moral philosophy is unlikely to be able to provide us with a definitive list, that at least part of duties we have to others will depend on the practices we happen to have. In any case, these underlying duties are not themselves duties of repair; they are duties of care. It is not a burden of corrective justice to identify or ground them. Quite the contrary, in fact. Once we have concrete requirements to take the interests of others into account in this or that way in regulating our own affairs, we face the altogether different question of whether, and in what ways, the breach of these duties impacts the normative relationships between the parties. What, in other words, are the normative consequences of a breach? Here is where the

Chapter 6 An Economic Theory of Tort Law

Chapter 6 An Economic Theory of Tort Law Chapter 6 An Economic Theory of Tort Law I. Defining Tort Law A. Intentional versus unintentional torts An intentional tort is one in which the defendant intended to cause harm to the plaintiff by an act

More information

University of Texas at Austin. From the SelectedWorks of Richard S. Markovits. Richard S. Markovits

University of Texas at Austin. From the SelectedWorks of Richard S. Markovits. Richard S. Markovits University of Texas at Austin From the SelectedWorks of Richard S. Markovits 2015 TORT-RELATED RISK COSTS AND THE FIRST-BEST ECONOMIC INEFFICIENCY OF THE HAND FORMULA FOR NEGLIGENCE: HOW TO FIX THE FORMULA

More information

Lecture 4. Introduction to the economics of tort law

Lecture 4. Introduction to the economics of tort law Lecture 4. Introduction to the economics of tort law Lecture outline What are torts? The elements of an actionable tort Different liability rules Properties of different liability rules Errors Risk aversion

More information

Professional Practice 544

Professional Practice 544 March 27, 2017 Professional Practice 544 Tort Law and Insurance Michael J. Hanahan Schiff Hardin LLP 233 S. Wacker, Ste. 6600 Chicago, IL 60606 312-258-5701 mhanahan@schiffhardin.com Schiff Hardin LLP.

More information

Chapter 2. Risk Identification. Enterprise Risk Management. Employment. Chapter 3 Page 1

Chapter 2. Risk Identification. Enterprise Risk Management. Employment. Chapter 3 Page 1 Chapter 2 Risk Identification Enterprise Risk Management Ultimate Objective of ERM is to handle risks that is harmonious with the strategic plan. Making pre loss arrangements for post loss resources. Need

More information

Chapter 7 Topics in the Economics of Tort Liability

Chapter 7 Topics in the Economics of Tort Liability Chapter 7 Topics in the Economics of Tort Liability I. Extending the Economic Model A. Relaxing the core assumptions of the model developed in the previous chapter 1. Decision makers are rational In order

More information

Psychology and the Objectives of Tort Law

Psychology and the Objectives of Tort Law Introduction The driver of one car rear- ends another, causing damage to both cars; the driver s liability insurance covers the cost of repairs. A jury debates the appropriate damage award for a baby who

More information

State Sales Tax. There are few forms of taxation that are more misunderstood than sales tax! We hope this article will help clear matters up.

State Sales Tax. There are few forms of taxation that are more misunderstood than sales tax! We hope this article will help clear matters up. State Sales Tax There are few forms of taxation that are more misunderstood than sales tax! We hope this article will help clear matters up. The first thing that should be considered about sales tax, is

More information

RECOGNITION OF GOVERNMENT PENSION OBLIGATIONS

RECOGNITION OF GOVERNMENT PENSION OBLIGATIONS RECOGNITION OF GOVERNMENT PENSION OBLIGATIONS Preface By Brian Donaghue 1 This paper addresses the recognition of obligations arising from retirement pension schemes, other than those relating to employee

More information

University of Texas at Austin. From the SelectedWorks of Richard S. Markovits. Richard S. Markovits. February 10, 2009

University of Texas at Austin. From the SelectedWorks of Richard S. Markovits. Richard S. Markovits. February 10, 2009 University of Texas at Austin From the SelectedWorks of Richard S. Markovits February 10, 2009 RISK COSTS AND THE FIRST-BEST- ALLOCATIVE-EFFICIENCY OF STRICT LIABILITY, OF VARIOUS "COVERAGE- ENHANCED"

More information

ANSWERS TO THE QUESTIONS IN THE COURSE GUIDE CPCU nd Edition CONTENTS. Assignment Title Page

ANSWERS TO THE QUESTIONS IN THE COURSE GUIDE CPCU nd Edition CONTENTS. Assignment Title Page ANSWERS TO THE QUESTIONS IN THE COURSE GUIDE CPCU 552 2 nd Edition 2015-2016 CONTENTS Assignment Title Page 1 Introduction to Commercial 7 Liability Insurance 2 Commercial General Liability 28 Insurance,

More information

Exercises. (b) Show that x* is increasing in D and decreasing in c. (c) Calculate x* for D=500 and c=10.

Exercises. (b) Show that x* is increasing in D and decreasing in c. (c) Calculate x* for D=500 and c=10. Exercises 1. Consider a unilateral care accident model in which the probability of an accident is given by p(x)=e x, where x is the level of injurer care, and e is the base of the natural logarithm. Let

More information

The Economic Structure of Tort Law: Market-based or Command and Control? Tze-Shiou Chien

The Economic Structure of Tort Law: Market-based or Command and Control? Tze-Shiou Chien The Economic Structure of Tort Law: Market-based or Command and Control? Tze-Shiou Chien I. Tort law is a branch of private law. The function of private law is to facilitate market transactions. Only in

More information

Trustee Liabilities Over-exposed?

Trustee Liabilities Over-exposed? Trustee Liabilities Over-exposed? Changes introduced under the new Charities Act have highlighted the personal risks trustees face in undertaking their duties. Andrew Studd takes a look. When the new Charities

More information

New Mexico Court of Appeals: Farm Laborer Exception to Workers Compensation Is Unconstitutional Factual Background

New Mexico Court of Appeals: Farm Laborer Exception to Workers Compensation Is Unconstitutional Factual Background New Mexico Court of Appeals: Farm Laborer Exception to Workers Compensation Is Unconstitutional A recent decision by the New Mexico Court of Appeals is receiving much attention from the agricultural industry.

More information

A Comment on One More Time: New York s Structured Settlement Statutes, Rent Seeking and. the Pro-Plaintiff Bias Draft date: 3/23/04

A Comment on One More Time: New York s Structured Settlement Statutes, Rent Seeking and. the Pro-Plaintiff Bias Draft date: 3/23/04 A Comment on One More Time: New York s Structured Settlement Statutes, Rent Seeking and the Pro-Plaintiff Bias Draft date: 3/23/04 Thomas R. Ireland Department of Economics, 408 SSB University of Missouri

More information

Annex I to the Commission Staff Working Paper

Annex I to the Commission Staff Working Paper Annex I to the Commission Staff Working Paper THE LEGAL SYSTEMS OF CIVIL LIABILITY OF STATUTORY AUDITORS IN THE EUROPEAN UNION Update of the study carried out on behalf of the Commission by Thieffry &

More information

SUMMARY ANALYSIS OF HB 5013: THE END OF NO-FAULT AS WE KNOW IT

SUMMARY ANALYSIS OF HB 5013: THE END OF NO-FAULT AS WE KNOW IT 216 North Chestnut Street, Lansing, MI 48933 (517) 882-1096 ProtectNoFault.com Facebook.com/ProtectNoFault Twitter.com/ProtectNoFault SUMMARY ANALYSIS OF HB 5013: THE END OF NO-FAULT AS WE KNOW IT By:

More information

Casualty (Liability) Basics

Casualty (Liability) Basics 3 Casualty (Liability) Basics LEARNING OBJECTIVES Upon the completion of this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Define basic casualty or liability insurance terms 2. Recognize the liability insurance principles

More information

Being a Guarantor. This booklet will help you understand all that is involved in being a Guarantor.

Being a Guarantor. This booklet will help you understand all that is involved in being a Guarantor. is a big responsibility and can have serious consequences. It is important to understand exactly what you are getting yourself into and what the impact of signing the agreement may be. can be a helpful

More information

V o l u m e I I C h a p t e r 5. Sections 10 and 11: Limitation of Actions, Elections, Subrogations and Certification to Court

V o l u m e I I C h a p t e r 5. Sections 10 and 11: Limitation of Actions, Elections, Subrogations and Certification to Court V o l u m e I I C h a p t e r 5 Sections 10 and 11: Limitation of Actions, Elections, Subrogations and Certification to Court Contents Limitation of Actions Against Workers... 5 Exception to Limitation

More information

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS ANDERSON MILES, Plaintiff-Appellant, UNPUBLISHED May 6, 2014 v No. 311699 Wayne Circuit Court STATE FARM MUTUAL AUTOMOBILE LC No. 10-007305-NF INSURANCE COMPANY, Defendant-Appellee.

More information

Business and Personal Finance Unit 4 Chapter Glencoe/McGraw-Hill

Business and Personal Finance Unit 4 Chapter Glencoe/McGraw-Hill 0 Chapter 13 Home and Motor Vehicle Insurance What You ll Learn Section 13.1 Identify types of risks and risk management methods. Explain how an insurance program can help manage risks. Describe the importance

More information

PERSONAL INJURY CASES

PERSONAL INJURY CASES Exceptional. Passionate. Trusted. PERSONAL INJURY ATTORNEYS THE BEGINNER S GUIDE TO PERSONAL INJURY CASES As personal injury lawyers, we ve seen many unique cases through the years. We ve found that an

More information

Fiduciary Duty: An Explosive Liability for Design Professionals

Fiduciary Duty: An Explosive Liability for Design Professionals Fiduciary Duty: An Explosive Liability for Design Professionals February 2012 Lockton Companies, LLC THE FIDUCIARY BOMB This paper is about fiduciary duties for design professionals, and has nothing to

More information

YOUR GUIDE TO PRE- SETTLEMENT ADVANCES

YOUR GUIDE TO PRE- SETTLEMENT ADVANCES YOUR GUIDE TO PRE- SETTLEMENT ADVANCES What is a pre-settlement advance? If you have hired an attorney to bring a lawsuit, and if you need cash now, you may be able to obtain a pre-settlement advance on

More information

Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty

Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty I. Probability and Expected Value Price Theory Lecture 9: Choice Under Uncertainty In all that we have done so far, we've assumed that choices are being made under conditions of certainty -- prices are

More information

Understanding Your Safety Responsibilities

Understanding Your Safety Responsibilities Understanding Your Safety Responsibilities Cameron Dean Partner McCullough Robertson Lawyers Background The enforcement of safety and health obligations in the Queensland mining industry by way of prosecutions

More information

VIABLE ADVANTAGES FOR ESTABLISHING A LIMITED LIABILITY COMPANY (LLC) IN NEVADA

VIABLE ADVANTAGES FOR ESTABLISHING A LIMITED LIABILITY COMPANY (LLC) IN NEVADA VIABLE ADVANTAGES FOR ESTABLISHING A LIMITED LIABILITY COMPANY (LLC) IN NEVADA As a natural consideration, entrepreneurs doing business in all types of industries want to pursue a business-building strategy

More information

Workplace Health and Safety Law in Australia Update No 2

Workplace Health and Safety Law in Australia Update No 2 University of Newcastle - Australia From the SelectedWorks of Neil J Foster October, 2012 Workplace Health and Safety Law in Australia Update No 2 Neil J Foster Available at: https://works.bepress.com/neil_foster/61/

More information

The Evolution of Fraud on the Market Suits and Halliburton II

The Evolution of Fraud on the Market Suits and Halliburton II The Evolution of Fraud on the Market Suits and Halliburton II Law and Economics of Capital Markets Fellows Workshop Columbia Law School Professor Merritt B. Fox September 11, 2014 Overview Nature of Fraud-on-the-market

More information

CORPORATE CRIMINAL LIABILITY: THEORY AND EVIDENCE

CORPORATE CRIMINAL LIABILITY: THEORY AND EVIDENCE NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository New York University Law and Economics Working Papers New York University School of Law 7-1-2011 CORPORATE CRIMINAL LIABILITY: THEORY AND EVIDENCE Jennifer Arlen

More information

California Bar Examination

California Bar Examination California Bar Examination Essay Question: Corporations/Contracts And Selected Answers The Orahte Group is NOT affiliated with The State Bar of California PRACTICE PACKET p.1 Question Beth, Charles, and

More information

The Timing of Present Value of Damages: Implications of Footnote 22 in the Pfeifer Decision

The Timing of Present Value of Damages: Implications of Footnote 22 in the Pfeifer Decision The Timing of Present Value of Damages: Implications of Footnote 22 in the Pfeifer Decision Thomas R. Ireland Department of Economics University of Missouri at St. Louis 8001 Natural Bridge Road St. Louis,

More information

Example: Swimming pools, ladders, refrigerators with doors left on, trampolines, and other kinds of property around a business or home.

Example: Swimming pools, ladders, refrigerators with doors left on, trampolines, and other kinds of property around a business or home. Chapter Three Casualty (Liability) Basics LEARNING OBJECTIVES Upon the completion of this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Define basic casualty or liability insurance terms 2. Recognize the liability

More information

Economic Analysis of Accident Law

Economic Analysis of Accident Law NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository Harvard Law School John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business Discussion Paper Series Harvard Law School 12-12-2002 Economic Analysis of Accident Law

More information

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW. Contracts. I.1 Bargain Theory. I.2 Damages Part 1. I.3 Reliance ECON 522 - DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW I Contracts When we were studying property law we were looking at situations in which the exchange of goods/services takes place at the time of trade, but sometimes

More information

CLAIMS AGAINST INDUSTRIAL HYGIENISTS: THE TRILOGY OF PREVENTION, HANDLING AND RESOLUTION PART TWO: WHAT TO DO WHEN A CLAIM HAPPENS

CLAIMS AGAINST INDUSTRIAL HYGIENISTS: THE TRILOGY OF PREVENTION, HANDLING AND RESOLUTION PART TWO: WHAT TO DO WHEN A CLAIM HAPPENS CLAIMS AGAINST INDUSTRIAL HYGIENISTS: THE TRILOGY OF PREVENTION, HANDLING AND RESOLUTION PART TWO: WHAT TO DO WHEN A CLAIM HAPPENS Martin M. Ween, Esq. Partner Wilson, Elser, Moskowitz, Edelman & Dicker,

More information

COMPENSATION SYSTEM IN SRI LANKA

COMPENSATION SYSTEM IN SRI LANKA CHAPTER 4: COMPENSATION SYSTEM IN SRI LANKA The procedure involve in post accident process in Sri Lanka is filing action in magistrate court by the police if the accident is not settle between parties.

More information

This document provides a brief summary of insider trading regulations in Japan and is intended

This document provides a brief summary of insider trading regulations in Japan and is intended This document provides a brief summary of insider trading regulations in Japan and is intended for educational purposes only. Contents have been recapitulated and omitted for perspicuity. Please consult

More information

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments

Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments Chapter 6: Supply and Demand with Income in the Form of Endowments 6.1: Introduction This chapter and the next contain almost identical analyses concerning the supply and demand implied by different kinds

More information

Introduction Pennsylvania Ave. NW Suite 700 Washington, D.C financialservices.org

Introduction Pennsylvania Ave. NW Suite 700 Washington, D.C financialservices.org Statement of Robin Traxler, Senior Vice President and Deputy General Counsel Financial Services Institute before the SEC Investor Advisory Committee December 13, 2018 Washington, D.C. Discussion Regarding

More information

A) Facts giving rise to liability

A) Facts giving rise to liability THE KIEV PROTOCOL ON CIVIL LIABILITY AND COMPENSATION FOR DAMAGE CAUSED BY THE TRANSBOUNDARY EFFECTS OF INDUSTRIAL ACCIDENTS ON TRANSBOUNDARY WATERS ACHIEVEMENTS AND PROSPECTS By: Phani Dascalopoulou-Livada,

More information

Environmental Economic Theory No. 8 (12 December 2017)

Environmental Economic Theory No. 8 (12 December 2017) Professional Career Program Environmental Economic Theory No. 8 (12 December 2017) Decentralized policies: Liability laws, property rights, voluntary action. Instructor: Eiji HOSODA Textbook: Barry.C.

More information

Going-Private Regulation in an Era of Round Trip Transactions: A Commentary

Going-Private Regulation in an Era of Round Trip Transactions: A Commentary Washington University Law Review Volume 70 Issue 2 Symposium on Corporate Law and Finance January 1992 Going-Private Regulation in an Era of Round Trip Transactions: A Commentary Victor Brudney Follow

More information

STATE FARM MUTUAL AUTOMOBILE INSURANCE COMPANY, Applicant

STATE FARM MUTUAL AUTOMOBILE INSURANCE COMPANY, Applicant CITATION: State Farm Mutual Automobile Insurance Company v. TD Home & Auto Insurance Company, 2016 ONSC 6229 COURT FILE NO.: CV-16-555100 DATE: 20161222 SUPERIOR COURT OF JUSTICE ONTARIO RE: STATE FARM

More information

DIEGO M. PAPAYANNIS Corrective Justice, Well-being, and Responsibility

DIEGO M. PAPAYANNIS Corrective Justice, Well-being, and Responsibility DIEGO M. PAPAYANNIS Corrective Justice, Well-being, and Responsibility ABSTRACT: In this paper I argue that Coleman s mixed conception of corrective justice is subject to three important objections. First,

More information

ON THE SOCIAL FUNCTION AND THE REGULATION OF LIABILITY INSURANCE. Steven Shavell. Discussion Paper No /2000

ON THE SOCIAL FUNCTION AND THE REGULATION OF LIABILITY INSURANCE. Steven Shavell. Discussion Paper No /2000 ISSN 1045-6333 ON THE SOCIAL FUNCTION AND THE REGULATION OF LIABILITY INSURANCE Steven Shavell Discussion Paper No. 278 3/2000 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138 The Center for Law, Economics, and

More information

JUDGMENT. [1] In the Court a quo the appellant was refused bail by the Port Elizabeth

JUDGMENT. [1] In the Court a quo the appellant was refused bail by the Port Elizabeth IN THE HIGH COURT OF SOUTH AFRICA EASTERN CAPE LOCAL DIVISION, PORT ELIZABETH Case no: CA&R15/2016 Date heard: 25 th January 2017 Date delivered: 2 nd February 2017 In the matter between: LUTHANDO MFINI

More information

DECISION AND REASONS

DECISION AND REASONS Upper Tribunal (Immigration and Asylum Chamber) Appeal Number: IA/17105/2012 THE IMMIGRATION ACTS Heard at Field House Determination Promulgated On 21 April 2015 On 10 June 2015 Before UPPER TRIBUNAL JUDGE

More information

Remedies and Administration of the Consumer Credit Law

Remedies and Administration of the Consumer Credit Law Louisiana Law Review Volume 34 Number 3 Employment Discrimination: A Title VII Symposium Symposium: Louisiana's New Consumer Protection Legislation Spring 1974 Remedies and Administration of the Consumer

More information

RISK ASSESSMENTS (GENERAL) POLICY AND GUIDANCE

RISK ASSESSMENTS (GENERAL) POLICY AND GUIDANCE RISK ASSESSMENTS (GENERAL) POLICY AND GUIDANCE Revised June 2016: Version 1.2 Name of Policy: Purpose of the Policy: Policy Applies to: Approved by: Responsible for its Updating: Final Approval by: Risk

More information

IN THE LABOUR COURT OF SOUTH AFRICA. (Held at Johannesburg) Case No: J118/98. In the matter between: COMPUTICKET. Applicant. and

IN THE LABOUR COURT OF SOUTH AFRICA. (Held at Johannesburg) Case No: J118/98. In the matter between: COMPUTICKET. Applicant. and IN THE LABOUR COURT OF SOUTH AFRICA (Held at Johannesburg) Case No: J118/98 In the matter between: COMPUTICKET Applicant and MARCUS, M H, NO AND OTHERS Respondents REASONS FOR JUDGMENT Date of Hearing:

More information

Alternative business entities: liability and insurance issues

Alternative business entities: liability and insurance issues Alternative business entities: liability and insurance issues TABLE OF CONTENTS I. PARTNERSHIPS...2 II. LIMITED LIABILITY COMPANIES...9 III. COVERAGE FOR AFFILIATES...12 i For liability, tax and operating

More information

Standard Decision Theory Corrected:

Standard Decision Theory Corrected: Standard Decision Theory Corrected: Assessing Options When Probability is Infinitely and Uniformly Spread* Peter Vallentyne Department of Philosophy, University of Missouri-Columbia Originally published

More information

Nuts & Bolts of Market Management

Nuts & Bolts of Market Management Farmers Market Managers Professional Certification Program Module 1: Unit 1.4 Nuts & Bolts of Market Management Understanding Liability Insurance UNIT OVERVIEW This unit will emphasize the risk management

More information

The Scope and Nature of Occupational Health and Safety

The Scope and Nature of Occupational Health and Safety Element 1: Foundations in Health and Safety The Scope and Nature of Occupational Health and Safety The study of health and safety involves the study of many different subjects including the sciences (chemistry,

More information

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2. Contracts. I.1 Investment in Performance

ECON DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2. Contracts. I.1 Investment in Performance ECON 522 - DISCUSSION NOTES ON CONTRACT LAW-PART 2 I Contracts I.1 Investment in Performance Investment in performance is investment to reduce the probability of breach. For example, suppose I decide to

More information

Public Sector Economics Test Questions Randall Holcombe Fall 2017

Public Sector Economics Test Questions Randall Holcombe Fall 2017 Public Sector Economics Test Questions Randall Holcombe Fall 2017 1. Governments should act to further the public interest. This statement would probably receive general agreement, but it is not always

More information

Chapter 33: Public Goods

Chapter 33: Public Goods Chapter 33: Public Goods 33.1: Introduction Some people regard the message of this chapter that there are problems with the private provision of public goods as surprising or depressing. But the message

More information

RHA Truck Cartel Claim

RHA Truck Cartel Claim RHA Truck Cartel Claim How to sign up to the RHA s group claim T: 08450 30 50 30 W: www.truckcartellegalaction.com E: truckcartel@rha.uk.net RHA Truck Cartel Claim 02 What is the RHA doing? truckcartellegalaction.com

More information

ECMC49S Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100

ECMC49S Midterm. Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100 ECMC49S Midterm Instructor: Travis NG Date: Feb 27, 2007 Duration: From 3:05pm to 5:00pm Total Marks: 100 [1] [25 marks] Decision-making under certainty (a) [10 marks] (i) State the Fisher Separation Theorem

More information

DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA COURT OF APPEALS BOARD ON PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY

DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA COURT OF APPEALS BOARD ON PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA COURT OF APPEALS BOARD ON PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY In the Matter of: : : HENDRITH V. SMITH, : Bar Docket No. 473-97 : Respondent. : REPORT AND RECOMMENDATION OF THE BOARD ON PROFESSIONAL

More information

It must be noted that: There is no difference in principle between «executive» and «non executive directors»,

It must be noted that: There is no difference in principle between «executive» and «non executive directors», BULLETIN 6 DUTIES AND LIABILITIES OF DIRECTORS UNDER CYPRUS LAW Cap. 113, Cyprus Companies Law, provides that every private company must have at least one director and every public company must have at

More information

Subjectivity and ability to pay tax in Consolidated ( 1 ).

Subjectivity and ability to pay tax in Consolidated ( 1 ). Subjectivity and ability to pay tax in Consolidated ( 1 ). The objective of this study is to assess the national institute of Consolidated governed by art. 117 ff. Tuir, with a view to resolving the sensitive

More information

Taxing Risk* Narayana Kocherlakota. President Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis. Economic Club of Minnesota. Minneapolis, Minnesota.

Taxing Risk* Narayana Kocherlakota. President Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis. Economic Club of Minnesota. Minneapolis, Minnesota. Taxing Risk* Narayana Kocherlakota President Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Economic Club of Minnesota Minneapolis, Minnesota May 10, 2010 *This topic is discussed in greater depth in "Taxing Risk

More information

A NOTE ON VOLUNTARY VERSUS INVOLUNTARY RISKS

A NOTE ON VOLUNTARY VERSUS INVOLUNTARY RISKS A NOTE ON VOLUNTARY VERSUS INVOLUNTARY RISKS CASS R. SUNSTEIN * Ordinary people seem to perceive voluntarily incurred risks as less troublesome than involuntarily incurred risks. Consider the diverse public

More information

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application

Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application Risk Aversion, Stochastic Dominance, and Rules of Thumb: Concept and Application Vivek H. Dehejia Carleton University and CESifo Email: vdehejia@ccs.carleton.ca January 14, 2008 JEL classification code:

More information

Pitfalls of Adding Clients or Other Design Professionals as Additional Insureds

Pitfalls of Adding Clients or Other Design Professionals as Additional Insureds BluePrint For Design Professionals Pitfalls of Adding Clients or Other Design Professionals as Additional Insureds By Thomas Hay and Kevin Kieffer Architects and engineers who obtain professional liability

More information

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations

Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations Chapter 19: Compensating and Equivalent Variations 19.1: Introduction This chapter is interesting and important. It also helps to answer a question you may well have been asking ever since we studied quasi-linear

More information

This exclusion protects the named insured, as well as its insurer, from

This exclusion protects the named insured, as well as its insurer, from Exclusion 2: 'The insurance does not apply to any person or organization, as insured, from whom the named insured has acquired such products or any ingredient, part or container, entering into, accompanying

More information

THE STATE OF NEW HAMPSHIRE SUPREME COURT. Docket No Terry Ann Bartlett

THE STATE OF NEW HAMPSHIRE SUPREME COURT. Docket No Terry Ann Bartlett THE STATE OF NEW HAMPSHIRE SUPREME COURT Docket No. 2014-0285 Terry Ann Bartlett v. The Commerce Insurance Company, Progressive Northern Insurance Company and Foremost Insurance Company APPEAL FROM FINAL

More information

Mistakes to Avoid If You Are in a Georgia Car Wreck

Mistakes to Avoid If You Are in a Georgia Car Wreck Mistakes to Avoid If You Are in a Georgia Car Wreck JAMES K. MURPHY Murphy Law Firm, LLC Georgia Accident & Injury Attorney 8302 Office Park Drive 2 Table of Contents: Preface: Who is Behind This Book,

More information

Health & Safety for Activities. Warning! Getting this wrong could cost YOU unbelievable amounts of money if you are sued for negligence

Health & Safety for Activities. Warning! Getting this wrong could cost YOU unbelievable amounts of money if you are sued for negligence Health & Safety for Activities Warning! Getting this wrong could cost YOU unbelievable amounts of money if you are sued for negligence Why??? Think of three good reasons why getting your H&S in order is

More information

DEBTS AND DISPUTES. Understanding Debt. What to do?

DEBTS AND DISPUTES. Understanding Debt. What to do? DEBTS AND DISPUTES If you ve ever been owed money, you know it s a frustrating situation to be in. Even when it s a small sum, debts not only leave a bad taste, but they can really affect your financial

More information

ESOP FIDUCIARY LIABILITY: AN OVERVIEW OF THE OBLIGATIONS AND EXPOSURES OF ESOP FIDUCIARIES. Prepared by Stephen D. Rosenberg, The Wagner Law Group 1

ESOP FIDUCIARY LIABILITY: AN OVERVIEW OF THE OBLIGATIONS AND EXPOSURES OF ESOP FIDUCIARIES. Prepared by Stephen D. Rosenberg, The Wagner Law Group 1 ESOP FIDUCIARY LIABILITY: AN OVERVIEW OF THE OBLIGATIONS AND EXPOSURES OF ESOP FIDUCIARIES Prepared by Stephen D. Rosenberg, The Wagner Law Group 1 Table of Contents Important Note... 1 Executive Summary...

More information

Contractual Confusion Assuming the Liability of Others

Contractual Confusion Assuming the Liability of Others Contractual Confusion Assuming the Liability of Others July 2009 To quote former major league pitcher Roger Clemens, sometimes we "misremember." This tendency is particularly embarrassing when you continue

More information

Law & Economics (Fall 2017; 4 credits; TuTh 10:30-12:20) Prof. Steve Calandrillo (206) ;

Law & Economics (Fall 2017; 4 credits; TuTh 10:30-12:20) Prof. Steve Calandrillo (206) ; Law & Economics (Fall 2017; 4 credits; TuTh 10:30-12:20) Prof. Steve Calandrillo (206) 685-2403; stevecal@uw.edu Office Hours (Room 419): TuTh 12:20-1:20, and by appointment (email stevecal@uw.edu) Course

More information

University of West Los Angeles Final Examination Business Organizations

University of West Los Angeles Final Examination Business Organizations Professor M. Jonathan Hayes Fall 2017 December -, 2017 6:30-8:30 pm University of West Los Angeles Final Examination Business Organizations QUESTION 1. (50%) Yoga, Inc. owns and operates 51 yoga studios

More information

Archery Victoria is mindful of the risks associated with conducting archery activities and events at club level.

Archery Victoria is mindful of the risks associated with conducting archery activities and events at club level. 0521. Risk Management Policy Archery Victoria Title: Policy and Procedures Manual Subject: Risk Management Policy Author: Chief Executive Officer - Trevor Filmer Date: 1-Jul-11 Replaces: 1-Jul-11 Number:

More information

Statement of Policy and Procedures Governing Trading in Shares of Prudential Bancorp, Inc.

Statement of Policy and Procedures Governing Trading in Shares of Prudential Bancorp, Inc. Statement of Policy and Procedures Governing Trading in Shares of Prudential Bancorp, Inc. QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS ABOUT INSIDER TRADING THE COVERAGE OF THE PROHIBITION Q: Does the insider trading prohibition

More information

Guide to Ohio Car Accident Law INJURY-0

Guide to Ohio Car Accident Law INJURY-0 Guide to Ohio Car Accident Law Contents 3. 4. 5. 6. Meet The Sawan & Sawan Family Legal Disclaimer Introduction First Steps 7. The Accident Report 8. Insurance Coverage 9. Collecting Evidence 10. Dealing

More information

NEGLIGENT SECURITY: WHAT YOU NEED TO KNOW ABOUT THEM

NEGLIGENT SECURITY: WHAT YOU NEED TO KNOW ABOUT THEM NEGLIGENT SECURITY: WHAT YOU NEED TO KNOW ABOUT THEM 1 The meeting ran longer than planned, and it is now nighttime. As you leave the building, you recall your car is parked off in a far one corner of

More information

The Timing of Present Value ofdamages: Implications of Footnote 22 in the Pfeifer Decision. Introduction

The Timing of Present Value ofdamages: Implications of Footnote 22 in the Pfeifer Decision. Introduction The Timing of Present Value ofdamages: Implications of Footnote 22 in the Pfeifer Decision Thomas R. Ireland Introduction Most forensic economists calculate the present value of damages as of the expected

More information

The PEICL: Precontractual information duties 1 I. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS

The PEICL: Precontractual information duties 1 I. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS The PEICL: Precontractual information duties 1 Prof. Dr. Herman Cousy KULEUVEN-University Belgium I. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS 1. The importance of the subject-matter. My task is to give some comments to a

More information

A REPORT ON PROTECTING YOUR ASSETS

A REPORT ON PROTECTING YOUR ASSETS T H E H E R I T A G E C O M P A N I E S Protecting Your Families Future A REPORT ON PROTECTING YOUR ASSETS WHITE PAPER 2008 telephone: 831-438-5047 fax: 831-438-3004 w w w. s a f e a n d s e c u r e a

More information

Public spending on health care: how are different criteria related? a second opinion

Public spending on health care: how are different criteria related? a second opinion Health Policy 53 (2000) 61 67 www.elsevier.com/locate/healthpol Letter to the Editor Public spending on health care: how are different criteria related? a second opinion William Jack 1 The World Bank,

More information

Law should promote the wellbeing of people. Tort law, which deals with accidents,

Law should promote the wellbeing of people. Tort law, which deals with accidents, Introduction Law should promote the wellbeing of people. Tort law, which deals with accidents, should reduce their cost and frequency an important matter, as accidents cause approximately 42 million hospital

More information

What is it. w The economic theory of tort law emphasizes precaution against these risks, deterrence.

What is it. w The economic theory of tort law emphasizes precaution against these risks, deterrence. What is it w Tort law is concerned with accidental injuries. Its purposes are twofold: to compensate victims and to deter unreasonably dangerous behavior, accidents (product liability, medical malpractice,

More information

Law & Economics (Fall 2015; 4 credits; TuTh 10:30-12:20) Prof. Steve Calandrillo (206) ;

Law & Economics (Fall 2015; 4 credits; TuTh 10:30-12:20) Prof. Steve Calandrillo (206) ; Law & Economics (Fall 2015; 4 credits; TuTh 10:30-12:20) Prof. Steve Calandrillo (206) 685-2403; stevecal@uw.edu Office Hours (Room 419): TuTh 12:30-1:20, and by appointment (email stevecal@uw.edu) Course

More information

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS LAKELAND NEUROCARE CENTERS, Plaintiff-Appellant, FOR PUBLICATION February 15, 2002 9:15 a.m. v No. 224245 Oakland Circuit Court STATE FARM MUTUAL AUTOMOBILE LC No. 98-010817-NF

More information

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals.

Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals. Theory of Consumer Behavior First, we need to define the agents' goals and limitations (if any) in their ability to achieve those goals. We will deal with a particular set of assumptions, but we can modify

More information

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY

CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY CONVENTIONAL FINANCE, PROSPECT THEORY, AND MARKET EFFICIENCY PART ± I CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 Foundations of Finance I: Expected Utility Theory Foundations of Finance II: Asset Pricing, Market Efficiency,

More information

REMINDER OF REIMBURSEMENT OBLIGATION

REMINDER OF REIMBURSEMENT OBLIGATION REMINDER OF REIMBURSEMENT OBLIGATION Dear Participant: You recently submitted a claim form on which you indicated that you were injured in a non-work related accident. When the Fund pays benefits to you

More information

Justice Department s Focus on Individual Responsibility Requires Broadening of Excess Side-A Difference-in-Conditions D&O Insurance Policies

Justice Department s Focus on Individual Responsibility Requires Broadening of Excess Side-A Difference-in-Conditions D&O Insurance Policies Justice Department s Focus on Individual Responsibility Requires Broadening of Excess Side-A Difference-in-Conditions D&O Insurance Policies By Tim Burns The results of the recent national elections may

More information

8:18-cv DCC Date Filed 01/03/18 Entry Number 1 Page 1 of 12

8:18-cv DCC Date Filed 01/03/18 Entry Number 1 Page 1 of 12 8:18-cv-00014-DCC Date Filed 01/03/18 Entry Number 1 Page 1 of 12 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF SOUTH CAROLINA ANDERSON/GREENVILLE DIVISION JONATHAN ALSTON and DARIUS REID, individually

More information

THOMAS M. STONE OPINION BY JUSTICE A. CHRISTIAN COMPTON v. Record No December 16, 1996

THOMAS M. STONE OPINION BY JUSTICE A. CHRISTIAN COMPTON v. Record No December 16, 1996 Present: All the Justices THOMAS M. STONE OPINION BY JUSTICE A. CHRISTIAN COMPTON v. Record No. 960412 December 16, 1996 LIBERTY MUTUAL INSURANCE COMPANY UPON A QUESTION OF LAW CERTIFIED BY THE UNITED

More information

Introduction. Valparaiso University Law Review. Jay Conison. Volume 34 Number 3. pp Summer Recommended Citation

Introduction. Valparaiso University Law Review. Jay Conison. Volume 34 Number 3. pp Summer Recommended Citation Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 34 Number 3 pp.555-559 Summer 2000 Introduction Jay Conison Recommended Citation Jay Conison, Introduction, 34 Val. U. L. Rev. 555 (2000). Available at: http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol34/iss3/5

More information

CASE STUDIES Germany

CASE STUDIES Germany CASE STUDIES Germany Tort claim example (1)... 1 Scenario 1... 1 Scenario 2A... 3 Scenario 2B... 4 Scenario 3... 4 Tort claim example (2)... 5 Scenario 4A... 5 Scenario 4B... 6 Scenario 4C... 6 Contract

More information